If We Were Immortal

Monday, 09-03-2018

 

Last semester some of my students asked whether, if it were possible, we should do something to our genes so that, barring accident, our lifespan was unlimited.

Our lifespan in this world, mind you.  It’s a tempting thought, but consider.

If we were immortal, no new generations would arise to replace us.

If we were immortal, we would become set in our ways and resist all new things.

If we were immortal, we would never learn anything.  We would never grow up.  We would think there was plenty of time.

At first we might condescend to having young to replace losses from accidental death.  Eventually even that would seem too great a burden.

We would forget the sound of childish laughter.

Sacrificial love would seem a scandal.

Bored with ourselves, closed unto ourselves, selfish as only fallen men can be, we would despair of this life, but we would have given up the hope of any other.

If we were immortal, we would probably die out quickly, and I say it would be good riddance.

Related posts:

What If We Changed Our Nature?

Why Shouldn’t We Transcend Our Nature?

 

Conference on Fatherhood

Saturday, 09-01-2018

 

Fatherhood is taking it in the chops these days, and fanatics use the term “patriarchy” as a synonym for oppression.  Against all that is this:

Patriarchy:  Fatherhood and the Restoration of Culture

Thursday 11 October – Saturday 13 October

Trinity International University, Deerfield, Illinois

I can hardly believe that the organizers were brave enough to give this conference the title “Patriarchy.”  Take that, you foes of fatherhood!  Doesn’t it give you a thrill?  But this isn’t going to be a chest-thumping festival.  Naturally, distortions of manhood and fatherhood will be discussed too.

Almost forgot to mention that along with fourteen other speakers, I’ll be giving one of the talks, on “What Makes Men Men.”

 

Varieties of Shame

Thursday, 08-30-2018

 

Shame is not the same as guilt – or perhaps it would be better to say that there are several kinds of shame.

To hide one’s sins from others really is the shame of guilt.  But to practice modesty is the shame of innocence.

Even as to the shame of guilt, a distinction must be made.  One might conceal his sins to escape the punishment he deserves.  But he might also conceal them to spare others exposure to his taint.

I wouldn’t condemn a man for that.

Related:

Trying to Shame the Shameless

What Conscience Isn’t

An Angry Professor

 

It Seems Like Straw

Monday, 08-27-2018

 

Query:

I am a Chinese scholar.  It is said that Thomas Aquinas gave up his research on rational theology before his death and confessed his research is nonsense and it means he retrogressed to Tertullian standpoint (embracing credo quia absurdum).  Is this true?

 

Reply:

Good question.  The view of Thomas Aquinas which you mention is quite common, but profoundly misleading.

At several points in his life, St. Thomas is said to have experienced divine visions.  In one of them, Christ appeared to him and said, “You have written well of me, Thomas.  What would you ask of me?”  St. Thomas replied, “Only you, Lord.”

Later, at the end of his life, he is said to have experienced another vision.  Afterward, he told one of his brothers in the Dominican order that he could no longer continue to write, because in comparison with what had been revealed to him, all that he had written seemed like straw.  This is the statement which gives rise to the misunderstanding about which you ask.

But it is very important to remember that St. Thomas never repudiated what he had written before.  Though his past writing seemed to him “like” straw in comparison with the vision, it was very good so far as it could go.  Straw itself is good.  The Bread of Heaven is better.

This should not surprise us.  Throughout his life, St. Thomas had always argued that what can be known about God by reasoning is excellent, but it is only about God.  The vision of God in Himself, granted to the souls of the redeemed in the next life, is infinitely superior.  Now that he was standing at the very door to that life, it was difficult for him to give his attention to anything less.

As St. Paul had written, in a passage which St. Thomas quoted often, “For now we see in a mirror dimly, but then face to face.  Now I know in part; then I shall understand fully, even as I have been fully understood.”

Related:

Reflection

Contentment

Move That Can Six Inches

 

Then Are All Good Men Good Statesmen?

Saturday, 08-25-2018

 

Query:

I read your argument that a bad man cannot be a good statesman – a theme I always enjoy bringing up when I teach.  There are interesting dilemmas, however.  I was not old enough to vote in 1972, but even knowing then what I know now, I do not believe a vote for McGovern could be justified -- which leaves me with Nixon.  But I see no other choice.  Your view?

 

Reply:

I take your point about voting for President Nixon instead of Senator McGovern even though Nixon was a scoundrel, but I don’t see the dilemma the same way you do.  I am only saying that a bad man cannot be a good statesman.  I am not saying that a good man is inevitably a good statesman.

The remark I’ve just made uses the term “good man” in your sense of the term.  By a good man, I think you mean someone who has all of the moral virtues, even though he may lack prudenceSenator McGovern certainly lacked prudence, and he would have made a terrible president.

But there is another, older way to take the meaning of the term “good man.”  For in the classical view, prudence is one of the moral virtues.  In fact, it is their intellectual pivot, because it is nothing more than the wisdom to know how to pursue the ends which the other virtues make us desire.  In this sense, a completely virtuous man is not one who possesses justice, fortitude, and temperance, even though he may lack prudence.  He is one who possesses justice, fortitude, temperance, and prudence.

Then would a good man in that sense inevitably be a good statesman?  The answer is still “No.”  Someone might be prudent in the everyday things with which we all have to deal, but not prudent in the larger matters which concern the body politic.  If he has all the other moral virtues, and moreover he has not just everyday prudence but also political prudence, then I would say yes, he has what it takes to be a good statesman – but not every ordinary good man does.  Far from it.

Related:

Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Virtue Ethics

 

Bad Men, Revisited

Thursday, 08-23-2018

 

Query:

I thought of your views today when I read today’s Town Hall column by Walter Williams, “Bad Men, Good Presidents.”

There have been many times in the past two years that I have wished that I could chat with you about the connection between moral character and political greatness – a connection you raised explicitly way back in the Clinton years.  Some day, perhaps.

 

Reply:

I would enjoy chatting too.  Thanks for your letter, and for calling my attention to Walter Williams’ essay. 

Mr. Williams argues that although the current president “does not have the personal character that we would want our children to imitate,” he “has turned out to be a good president, save his grossly misguided international trade policies.”  Some of the actions for which Williams praises the president are making good nominations to the U.S. Supreme Court, significantly rolling back federal regulations, ending the Obamacare “mandate,” and getting the United States out of the fraudulent nuclear deal with Iran.

Of course Williams recognizes that Left will view the same actions as “horrible, maybe treasonous,” but does not trouble me; I don’t agree with the Left.  Regarding some of the other things Williams approves, such as making a sort of progress with Kim Jong Un, I think Williams’ judgment is premature, but certainly the old policy appeasing the tyrant in return for promises no one expected him to keep wasn’t working.

So should I change my view that a bad man cannot be a good statesman?  No.

Trump apologists always overlook the same problems with bad men.  Williams’ view of a good president is one who does more good things than bad ones.  If that’s what a good president is, then of course a bad man can be a good president.

But it’s the wrong criterion.  When people like me say a bad man cannot be a good president, that is not what they mean.  I have never denied that a bad man can do some good things.  In fact I’ve insisted on it.

So what is the problem?

As I wrote in an earlier post, “in the first place, the bad man’s motive is flawed, so if it suits his purposes, he is just as likely to do something evil.  You cannot be confident that he will do the right thing.”

“In the second place,” I wrote, “just because his motive is flawed, even when he does intend a good act, he is likely to do it in an evil way.”

Moreover, “there are some good things he cannot do even if they do chance to coincide with his motives.  For example, he cannot successfully promote good character in others, and will probably injure it by example.”

“Besides,” I concluded, “No matter what he does, he will lie to you about it.”

I see no reason to withdraw any of these points.  The third is especially important.  Trump’s vices drag all of us down, just as Clinton’s did a generation ago.

Conceded, the view I am defending is not popular on either side of the political schism.  On both the Left and Right, activists think that a thug is all right so long as he is our thug.

Couldn’t there be reasons for voting for a bad man?  Yes, of course.  If both candidates are depraved, but there is good reason to believe that one of them may tend to do better things than the other, then provided that voting for him does not involve formal cooperation with evil, one should vote for him.  In that sense, sure, we will have to see how things work out with Mr. Trump.

But no one should deceive himself that doing the things that we want him to do will make him a good president.

See also:

What It Really Means to Be Great

But He’s Our Thug, Take 2

Does Peggy Noonan Read This Blog?

Talk:  The Problem with Liberalism – and Conservatism

Pravda

Monday, 08-20-2018

 

Those who hold the views dominant among university faculty often mock those who comment -- well, on the fact that their views are dominant among university faculty.  Recently I came across the statement that when persons like me complain about the overwhelming prevalence of secular leftist ideologies in the classroom, we are really merely complaining that students at universities “meet real life.”

No, we are complaining that the students there don’t meet real life.  Real life includes all sorts of people with all sorts of ideas.  Academia doesn’t.

Is the “meeting real life” excuse merely naïve, or is it offered in bad faith?  Maybe a little of both.

You can see why some scholars might want to believe that they represent “real life.”  If they were ever to admit to themselves how they shut out the views they dislike, it would eat away at their picture of themselves as critics of the “narratives of power” and protectors of society’s underdogs (of whom, by the way, most have little first-hand knowledge and even less respect).

On the other hand, it seems likely that many university people really don’t know how narrow their intellectual culture is.  Since the only people they ever meet are just like them, they think they represent the Great Center, and that their little end of the spectrum is the whole universe of reasonable discourse.

By the way, they censor themselves just as ruthlessly as they do others.  If a scholar of this sort ever catches himself implying that there might be something questionable about some behavior that PC norms hold sacrosanct – yes, it happens – he hastens to cover himself by saying, “Not that there’s anything wrong with that.”  And he tries to believe that this is true.

Not only does his social place depend on covering himself, but so does his sense of himself as someone who belongs.

Related posts:

The Future of the Life of the Mind

Thick Descriptions, Thin Skins