The Problem with Liberalism – And Conservatism

Monday, 04-24-2017

 

A good many Christians treat either liberal or conservative ideology as the authentic political expression of Christianity.  For example, the left tends to view having compassion for the poor as practically identical with being liberal, and the right tends to view having respect for 'traditional values' as more or less the same thing as being conservative.  Back in the ‘nineties, I wrote a pair of articles for First Things magazine to explore the problem -- one called “The Problem with Liberalism,” the other “The Problem with Conservatism.”  Last year, The Austin Institute for the Study of Family and Culture asked me, not to give a rehash of the articles, but to reflect on the problems with liberalism and conservatism today.  They talked First Things into sponsoring the lecture, and I’ll be giving it this very week.

The date is Thursday, April 27.  The time is 5:30pm.  The location is The University of Texas at Austin, Flawn Academic Center (FAC) Room 21, 2304 Whitis Ave #338, Austin, Texas.  If you’d like to come, you can register to attend here.  I hope you can come.

 

From an Easter Homily of Thomas Aquinas

Monday, 04-17-2017

 

The Lord is Risen!  This is an abbreviated outline of one of Thomas Aquinas’s homilies for the season of Easter.  Besides being crisp and illuminating, it shows how he labored to extract every last grain of meaning from every pronouncement of Scripture.  I think it’s an excellent model.

+++++  +  +++++

Christ said, “I came from the Father and have come into the world; again, I am leaving the world and going to the Father." – John 16:28.

He “came forth from the Father” for three reasons:  To He might manifest the Father in the world; to declare His Father's will to us; and to show the Father's love towards us.

He “came into the world” for three reasons:  To enlighten it; to reconcile it to God the Father; and to deliver it from the power of the Devil.

He “left the world” for three reasons:  Because of its wickedness; because of the perversity of its ingratitude; and to give us an example – “Do not love the world or the things in the world”; “You are not of the world, but I chose you out of the world.”

He “ascended to the Father” for three reasons:  That he might intercede with Him for us; that He might give to us the Holy Spirit; and that He might prepare for us a place with the Father.

To which place may He lead us.  Amen.

New Book

 

The Blade, the Ear, and the Corn

Sunday, 04-09-2017

 

Thomas Aquinas believed the relation among natural law, Old Testament law, and New Testament law to have been well expressed by John Chrysostom’s commentary on Mark 4:28, that God “brought forth first the blade, i.e. the Law of Nature; then the ear, i.e. the Law of Moses; lastly, the full corn, i.e. the Law of the Gospel.”  In other words, what is implicit in the natural law is made explicit in the Old Law and brought to glowing maturity in the New.

The practical implications of this blending of natural and Divine law are brought out in a strangely lovely way in St. Thomas’s own com­mentary on Christ’s remark, “But know this, that if the householder had known in what part of the night the thief was coming, he would have watched and would not have let his house be broken into” (Matthew 24:43):

“The house is the soul, in which man should be at rest. ‘When I go into my house,’ that is, my conscience, ‘I shall find rest with her [that is, Wisdom].’  The householder of the house is like the ‘king who sits on the throne of judgment,’ who ‘winnows away all evil with his eyes.’   Sometimes the thief breaks into the house.  The thief is any persuasive false doctrine or temp­tation .... Properly speaking, the door is natural knowledge, in other words, nat­ural right.  Therefore, anyone who enters through reason, enters through its door, but anyone who enters through the door of concupiscence or irascibility or some such thing, is a thief.  Thieves usually come at night.  As Obadiah says, ‘If thieves came to you, if plunderers by night – how you have been destroyed!’  So if they come in the day, do not fear.  In other words, temptations do not come when a man is contemplating divine things; but when he relaxes, they come.  For this reason, the prophet rightly says, “forsake me not when my strength is spent.”

New Book

 

Is Revelation Reasonable?

Monday, 04-03-2017

 

The fact that we are directed to behave virtuously through reason may make it mysterious why Divine instruction is necessary at all.  Here it is good to remember that faith is not the constriction of reason by blind dogma, as our own time so often views it.  Rather it is the unshackling of reason by grace, and its enlargement by the data of Revelation.  Reason is not only set free from sin, but also given more to work with.

But the fact that Revelation exceeds what we could have figured out for ourselves introduces a puzzle.  How can it be reasonable to submit to help from beyond human reason?

In at least five ways.

1.  Since the reality, power, wisdom, and goodness of God can be phil­osophically demonstrated, it is reasonable to consider Revelation possible.

2.  Since, even though we have a natural inclination to seek the truth about Him, our finite minds, still further weighed down by self-deception, could never equal His infinite mind, it is reasonable to consider Revelation necessary.

3.  Since He who gave us the inclination to seek Him must desire us to find Him, it is reasonable to consider Revelation likely.

4.  Since the record of Revelation is well-attested by miracles, it is rea­sonable to believe Revelation authentic.

5.  Since faith is accompanied by the experience of grace, it is reason­able to believe Revelation confirmed. The Psalmist cries, “O taste and see that the Lord is good!” Expressing the same thought in a different key, St. Paul exhorts, “test everything; hold fast what is good.”

By the light of Revelation, the mind is not only able to see more clearly those things that lie within its natural reach, but is also able to under­stand and explain many other features of the world that would oth­erwise have remained utterly baffling, such as why our hearts are so divided against themselves. When reason rejects Revelation, it is not being more true but less true to itself; only illuminated by God can it come into its own.

The hope of faith is that one day our thoughts may be lit not only by the reflected light of Revelation, but by the direct illumination of face of God Himself: That although now our minds only smolder, one day they will blaze with fire.

New Book

 

Giggling into the Abyss

Monday, 03-27-2017

 

There was a certain inevitability in existentialism’s decline, but at least the early existentialists were serious.  I count four stages in the philosophy's devolution.

1.  One must choose between hope and despair.

Soren Kierkegaard, 1847:  “To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of the good is to hope.  To relate oneself expectantly to the possibility of evil is to fear.  By the decision to choose hope one decides infinitely more than it seems, because it is an eternal decision.”

2.  But there is no ultimate ground for the decision.

Albert Camus, 1942:  “There is only one really serious philosophical question, and that is suicide.”

3.  So what?

Thomas Nagel, 1971:  “If sub specie aeternitatis there is no reason to believe that anything matters, then that doesn’t matter either.”

4.  Giggling into the abyss.

Jailblimp, an absurdist promotional video, 2017:  The descent of a little girl’s birthday party into bizarre and inexplicable events evokes no reaction from her except to check out her presents.

Subscribe

 

 

Thomas Aquinas’s Virtue Ethics

Monday, 03-20-2017

 

My new book, Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Virtue Ethics, is coming out from Cambridge University Press on April 30, and you can preorder right here.

By the way, my previous book, Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Treatise on Law, is now available in paperback, and my Companion to the Commentary is available online for free.  The book even has a trailer on YouTube.  But most of you know all that already.

Back to the new book.  Here is the description:

Although St Thomas Aquinas famously claimed that his Summa Theologiae was written for “beginners”, contemporary readers find it unusually difficult.  Now, amid a surge of interest in virtue ethics, J. Budziszewski clarifies and analyzes the text's challenging arguments about the moral, intellectual, and spiritual virtues, with a spotlight on the virtue of justice.  In what might be the first contemporary commentary on Aquinas's virtue ethics, he juxtaposes the original text with paraphrase and detailed discussion, guiding us through its complex arguments and classical rhetorical figures.  Keeping an eye on contemporary philosophical issues, he contextualizes one of the greatest virtue theorists in history and brings Aquinas into the interdisciplinary debates of today.  His brisk and clear style illuminates the most crucial of Aquinas' writings on moral character and guides us through the labyrinth of this difficult but pivotal work.

And here are its contents:

Part I:  Moral Character in General

Commentary on I-II, Question 55, Article 4:

Whether virtue is suitably defined?

St. Thomas investigates whether the traditional understanding of virtue, derived from St. Augustine of Hippo via Peter Lombard, is correct.  He considers six possible objections, concerning whether virtue is a good quality, whether it is a quality of the mind, whether it enables us to live rightly, whether it is possible for it to be employed badly, and whether it is brought about in us by God.  To solve the problem, he works out the formal, material, final, and efficient causes of virtue.

Commentary on I-II, Question 58, Article 4:

Whether there can be moral without intellectual virtue?

Can a person who lacks intellectual virtue still possess moral virtues such as fortitude, temperance, and justice?  For a variety of reasons, at first it seems that this is possible.  For example, common observation suggests that some people who do not reason well are morally virtuous.  However, Thomas shows that although not all intellectual virtues are necessary for moral virtue, the intellectual virtues of prudence and understanding are necessary for moral virtue.

Commentary on I-II, Question 58, Article 5:

Whether there can be intellectual without moral virtue?

The previous chapter asked whether a person who lacks intellectual virtue can still possess moral virtue; conversely, this chapter asks whether a person who lacks moral virtue can still possess intellectual virtue.  St. Thomas considers a variety of reasons for thinking that this may be possible, having to do with moral development, with the similarity between moral deeds and craftsmanship, and with the common observation that some people who lack moral virtue seem to advise themselves well.  He concludes, however, that although other intellectual virtues can exist without moral virtue, the intellectual virtue of prudence does require moral virtue.  Taking this chapter together with the previous one, we see that neither complete moral virtue nor complete intellectual virtue is possible without the other.

Commentary on I-II, Question 61, Article 2:

Whether there are four cardinal virtues?

According to a widely held view, all moral virtues pivot or depend on four pivotal or paramount virtues – prudence, justice, temperance, and fortitude -- sometimes called “cardinal” virtues after the Latin word for a hinge.  If true, this fact would provide a much more powerful way of understanding the virtues than had been offered by the influential philosopher Aristotle -- who, after helpfully suggesting that each moral virtue is a “mean” between opposite extremes, had presented a diffuse list of twelve “means” without explaining why he listed just these twelve and not others.  Responding to various objections, St. Thomas presents compelling reasons for thinking that the four virtues called cardinal surpass the other moral virtues and are, in a certain sense, their heads.  The first is prudence, or practical wisdom, the bridge between the moral and intellectual virtues, which brings the power of moral reasoning to its full and proper development.  The other three are fortitude, or courage; temperance, or restraint; and justice, or fairness.  All of the other “acquired” virtues are associated in some way with these four (as we will find later that all of the “infused” virtues are associated in some way with faith, hope, and charity).

Commentary on I-II, Question 61, Article 3:

Whether any other virtues should be called principal rather than these?

Some have suggested that although it is correct to think that all of the acquired moral virtues depend on a smaller number of cardinal virtues, nevertheless certain other virtues besides prudence, fortitude, temperance, and justice should also be called cardinal.  Magnanimity has been proposed because it spurs great acts of every virtue; humility, because it gives firmness to every virtue; and patience, because it is through patience that the acts of every other virtue are fully carried out.  Without in any way disparaging magnanimity, humility, or patience, St. Thomas argues that the fourfold list of cardinal virtues should be left as it stands.  Not only are these four concerned with matters of paramount importance, but every other moral virtue turns out to depend on them.  In particular, magnanimity and patience turn out to be aspects of the cardinal virtue of fortitude, and humility turns out to be an aspect of the cardinal virtue of temperance.

Commentary on I-II, Question 62, Article 1:

Whether there are any theological virtues?

Besides the four cardinal virtues, the classical tradition had identified three “theological” or spiritual virtues:  Faith, hope, and charity or love.  The suggestion that we may need spiritual virtues over and above the ordinary qualities of good character is ridiculous to the secular sort of mind.  Do such virtues exist?  In one sense, it may seem obvious that they exist, but care is needed because the popular culture gives each of these terms different meanings than what the tradition intends.  Confidence that my friend will not betray me is not the spiritual virtue of faith; optimism that I will get a raise in salary is not the spiritual virtue of hope; giving money to worthy causes is not the definition of charity; and even though the merely natural loves are good, the love called charity is different from the love of a man and a woman, the love of a mother for her child, or the love of two friends.  St. Thomas shows that in their correct meanings, the three theological virtues are genuine, and that they bear the same relation to the virtues infused by Divine grace that the cardinal virtues bear to the virtues acquired by human effort.

Commentary on I-II, Question 63, Article 1:

Whether virtue is in us by nature?

Is virtue implanted in the constitution of human beings -- does it in some sense belong to us just because we possess a human nature?  The query sounds very modern:  Many secular people believe that we are naturally good, and corrupted only by some disorder of social life which might perhaps be corrected by social engineering.  According to Christianity, the human condition is much more complex, for although we were endowed by the Creator with a good nature, this good gift is presently in bad condition.  A further complication is that although the term “natural” is sometimes used for things we do without having to learn them, it is also used for things we must learn in order to reach our full and appropriate development.  In the former sense, it is “natural” to breath; in the latter sense, it is “natural” to make friends.  St. Thomas responds to the query not just theologically but also philosophically, considering what it means for something to be true of us “by nature,” reviewing the history of the problem from the pre-Socratic philosopher Anaxagoras to his own time, and finally disentangling the senses in which virtue can and cannot be called natural to human beings.

Commentary on I-II, Question 63, Article 2:

Whether any virtue is caused in us by habituation?

According to the tradition, the “acquired” virtues are brought about in us by practicing the acts which correspond to them until they become habitual.  Is this true?  Up to this point in his discussion, St. Thomas has assumed the habituation hypothesis to be correct; in the present chapter, he scrutinizes it to find out whether it really is.  He takes up and discusses various reasons for thinking that it is false, for example the theological argument that apart from Divine grace humans can do nothing to become virtuous, and the metaphysical argument that a cause (in this case repeated acts) cannot be more perfect than its effect (in this case complete virtue).  His solution depends on a distinction between virtues which are directed to the good as measured by the rule of human reason, and virtues which are directed to the good as measured by the Divine law.  The former can be brought about by habituation; the latter can be brought about in us only by the work of God Himself.

Commentary on I-II, Question 65, Article 1:

Whether the moral virtues are connected with each other?

Can we pick and choose among the virtues -- is it possible to possess some of them without the others?  The classical tradition supposes that this is impossible; if you are defective in any virtue, then to some degree you will be defective in each of them, so that if you are serious about cultivating any of them you must cultivate all of them.  Yet today, we often view the virtues as disconnected, saying things like “He may be a crooked businessman, but he’s good to his mom,” “Even a bad man can be a good statesman,” and “There is honor among thieves.”  St. Thomas takes very seriously the reasons for thinking that the classical view is false, for example, the everyday observation that a man may perform the acts of one virtue without performing the acts of another.  Ultimately, however, Thomas defeats the objections by distinguishing between fully developed virtues, and merely incipient or incomplete virtues.  The former really are mutually dependent and interconnected; the latter are not.  He shows that this conclusion can be reached in two different ways, depending on the precise method adopted for distinguishing among the cardinal virtues.

Commentary on I-II, Question 84, Article 4:

Whether the seven capital vices are suitably reckoned?

Capital vices are those from which other vices arise; they are like leaders and directors of all the other vices.  Just as we must practice all of the virtues to be fully developed in any of them, so we cannot let one vice into the house without opening the door wide to its brothers.  The question in this chapter, however, is not so much whether certain vices should be considered capital, but which vices they are.  The tradition had viewed seven vices as capital:  Vainglory, envy, anger, sloth, covetousness, gluttony, and luSt. Various reasons can be offered for thinking either that this list is defective, some obvious (for example that since there are four cardinal virtues, there must be four capital vices), some not so obvious (for example that although gluttony and lust concern pleasure, and sloth and envy concern sadness, the list should also include vices pertaining to the other chief passions, hope and fear).  By means of a subtle and multifaceted analysis of the psychology of sin as a distortion of the natural desire for happiness, St. Thomas defends the traditional enumeration, comparing the seven capital vices to seven generals with pride as their queen.

Part II:  The Virtue of Justice, Especially in Relation to Law

Commentary on II-II, Question 30, Article 3:

Whether mercy is a virtue?

The classical tradition has considered mercy a virtue.  But is it?  At first it seems not.  In the first place, pity, like anger, can impede deliberation.  In the second place, the virtue of justice involves punishment, but mercy involves remission of punishment.  Besides, even if the acts of mercy are meritorious, it might be argued that they are merely effects of another virtue, so that mercy is not a virtue in itself.  In careful response to these objections, St. Thomas shows that the virtue of mercy is as genuine as the virtue of justice.  Although unregulated passion may indeed impede deliberation, the virtue of mercy is neither unregulated nor a passion.  Moreover, far from being an impediment to justice, mercy may actually serve the purposes of justice, provided that certain conditions are met.  Finally, mercy is not merely an effect of charity, but a distinct virtue subordinate to charity, for it concerns a particular mode in which the acts of charity are carried out.

Commentary on II-II, Question 58, Article 1:

Whether justice is fittingly defined as being the perpetual and constant will to render to each one his right?

According to a long tradition, justice is “a constant and perpetual will to give to each person his right.”  In our day the expression “right” is most often used to signify a liberty to do something, for example the right to bear arms, to speak freely, or to worship according to conscience.  In the classical definition of justice, however, the term is used in a much broader sense:  A person’s “right” is whatever is his, whatever he deserves, whatever is properly due to him.  The present chapter’s query is whether this time-honored formula suitably expresses the essence of justice.  St. Thomas considers six objections, each of which targets some element in the definition.  Objections One and Two deny that justice “a will”; Objection Three denies that it is “perpetual”; Objection Four, that it is both “perpetual” and “constant,” as though these words signified different qualities; and Objections Five and Six, that it “renders to each one his right.”

Commentary on II-II, Question 60, Article 1:

Whether judgment is an act of justice?

Before I can render someone what is due to him, I have to know what is due to him.  So the act of giving him his right seems to presuppose a prior act of judging what his right is.  Then is judgment itself the characteristic act of justice?  So it would seem, yet this answer lays us open to difficulties.  For example, if judging is an act of the intellect, wouldn’t it be the characteristic act of an intellectual rather than a moral virtue?  And isn’t some kind of judgment required by every virtue, not only by judgment?  On the other hand, judgment seems to be what judges do.  Where then does this leave the rest of us – is no one just but the judge?  To complicate matters still further, it might even be said that judgment belongs neither to the ordinary person nor to the judge, for St. Paul says that judgment, in some sense, is the act of “the spiritual man.”  We see then that what might at first appear to be a fatuous question – “Is judgment the characteristic act of justice?” – turns out to be a stumper.  St. Thomas unravels the difficulties.

Commentary on II-II, Question 60, Article 2:

Whether it is lawful to judge?

Human law appoints certain persons judges, but is it really right for any mere human to stand in judgment?  The Objectors think that the answer should be “No”; in their view, human judgment is condemned both by natural and Divine law.  In the relativistic ambiance of our own times as well, “judgmentalism” has been judged and found wanting.  Yet there is a certain difficulty with antijudgmentalism, for if no one may judge others, then how is it that we may deliver an unfavorable judgment upon those who do judge others?  Could it be that we have passed judgment upon judgment too quickly – or perhaps that only certain kinds of judgment are illicit?  If so, which kinds?  St. Thomas investigates the various senses in which human beings may and may not “judge.”

Commentary on II-II, Question 60, Article 5:

Whether we should always judge according to the written law?

The act of judgment is the means by which justice is actualized, and justice is in turn connected with all the rest of the virtues.  Normally, we should do as the written law directs, but earlier in the Summa St. Thomas has considered exceptions:  (1) Under certain conditions custom can abolish written law.  (2) Under certain conditions one may disobey so-called unjust laws, and may even be obligated to disobey them.  (3) When cases arise which the written law was not intended to cover, those who have the authority to make the law may also suspend it.  (4) In emergencies, when such cases arise but there is no time to consult authority, the citizens themselves may set aside the words of the law and follow its intention instead.  Here, though, St. Thomas is not thinking of either lawmakers or ordinary citizens.  Must judges follow the written law?  And must they do as its very words direct, or may they sometimes set aside the words and follow its intention instead?  This inquiry is not just about constitutional rules or judicial role definitions.  Taken in its broadest sense it concerns how such matters are related to human moral character.

Commentary on II-II, Question 60, Article 6:

Whether judgment is rendered perverse by being usurped?

Is justice destroyed when judgment is usurped – when a person is judged by someone who has no public authority to do so?  Usurpation of judgment is judging a case without jurisdiction, seizing the power of judgment from the person to whom it belongs.  However, in the present chapter St. Thomas is not asking whether it is unjust for a judge to make the sorts of judgments which properly belong to, say, the legislature; he has already established that this is wrong, because the judge must render judgment according to the law.  Rather he is asking whether it is unjust for someone else to make the sorts of judgments which properly belong to the judge himself.  The usurper, the “someone else,” might be another judge who has no jurisdiction in the case, or it might be someone who is not a judge at all.  St. Thomas defends the traditional view that the usurpation of judgment is a violation of justice -- that judging without proper jurisdiction always destroys justice -- even if the usurper renders the correct judgment.

Commentary on II-II, Question 80, Article 1:

Whether the virtues annexed to justice are suitably enumerated?

Although the many aspects of justice may be called “parts” of justice, they are not all “parts” in the same sense.  The present chapter is about the “potential” parts of justice, meaning the secondary virtues which in some way resemble justice or are associated with it.  Before St. Thomas, the thinkers who had investigated the potential parts of justice had enumerated them in a bewildering variety of ways.  In the present Article, he defends the sixfold classification of Marcus Tullius Cicero against the sevenfold classification of Macrobius, the ninefold classification of Pseudo-Andronicus, the fivefold classification of “certain others” whom he does not name, and a single suggestion drawn from Aristotle.  Characteristically, he does not simply discard the thoughts of all these others; whenever he comes upon a worthy insight, he works out what the writer was getting at and finds room for it in a subtler scheme to which the present chapter is merely an introduction.

Commentary on II-II, Question 122, Article 1:

Whether the precepts of the Decalogue are precepts of justice?

The notion of some people that virtue ethics is a way of doing ethics without rules would strike St. Thomas as very strange, for the acts to which the virtues predispose us are things which we ought to do; he always connects virtues with precepts, dispositions of character with authoritative rules.  In the present chapter he is concerned with the famous set of authoritative rules known as the Ten Commandments.  Although they are part of Divine law, Thomas thinks they are also precepts of natural law, upheld by reason.  The great question of the chapter -- whether they are precepts of justice – should be taken not in the sense “Do they have anything to do with justice?” but in the sense “Is justice is their main concern?”  For according to the classical tradition, the Divine law addresses all of the virtues, not only justice -- yet in some sense the Ten Commandments specialize in the virtue of justice.  What Thomas investigates is whether this view of their special concern is correct.

 

A Question for the Teachers of the Church

Monday, 03-13-2017

 

Why doesn’t the social witness of the Church have more influence than it does?  With respect, I suggest that perhaps one reason is that sometimes those who represent the Church speak as though they don’t believe her social doctrine.

Case in point:  The social doctrine of the Church distinguishes between just and unjust wars, recognizing that sometimes, as a last resort, the state must come out fighting.  As the Catechism states, “All citizens and all governments are obliged to work for the avoidance of war.  However, as long as the danger of war persists and there is no international authority with the necessary competence and power, governments cannot be denied the right of lawful self-defense, once all peace efforts have failed.”

In the view of the Church, just war is the right and necessary use of violence against another state, by public authority, subject to rigorous moral standards, for the sake of a just peace.

Why then does the highest representative of the Church declare that “faith and violence are incompatible”?  I think the prisoners who were liberated from the Nazi death camps by the United States Third Army might have found it puzzling to hear that “Never has the use of violence brought peace in its wake.”

Taken at face value, such statements do not simply urge working for peace, avoiding war when possible, or waging war only justly.  They obliterate the very distinction between just and unjust war.  They further imply that every soldier is in a state of mortal sin.  Such a teaching would not be a development of doctrine; it would be a reversal or annulment of doctrine.

Of course, no pope has the authority to reverse or annul doctrine, and according to a fundamental Catholic interpretive principle, papal statements should be read in continuity with what has always been held.  So I do not suggest that the Holy Father does want to do this thing.

But it is not unreasonable to ask why he speaks so carelessly as to give such an impression.  Four years into his papacy, he speaks in this confusing way about a growing number of topics.

I do not wish to exhibit anything less than respect.  It could not be easy to be the Vicar of Christ, not only responsible for the spiritual direction of 1.3 billion Catholics, but also a visible symbol of the hope for unity among all Christians.  I see, too, that he is seeking ways to communicate the Gospel more forcefully.

Yet surely it is not too much for the faithful to ask the Church’s highest teachers to express themselves in ways that clarify the Church’s teaching instead of scrambling it.

Archives