Polarized

Sunday, 05-20-2018

 

I usually post on Mondays.

Never underestimate the brutal power of desperation, on either the right or the left.

Early in the previous presidential administration, a young man showed up during my office hours to tell me his strategy for overcoming the other side in the culture wars.  He wasn’t one of my students, and I don’t know why he sought me out.  I suppose he thought I would be sympathetic.

Having learned about the lessons the then-president is supposed to have learned from community organizer Saul Alinsky, he said “Our side has to do that stuff too.”

What sort of stuff?  He meant things like threatening, lying about one’s goals, misrepresenting the other side’s positions, assassinating the character of opponents, and deliberately provoking crises in order to make people frantic for change.

As you may know, a lot of people since then have taken the same view.  Culture wars ignite cultural arms races.

Desperation.

I told him I didn’t believe in doing evil so that good would result.

But they’re destroying the country.  We have to save it.

How would it save the country to become just like the people he viewed as destroying it?

But they’re winning.  We can’t let them win.

What would he expect to win by destroying the moral order of the republic he claimed to love?

He demanded to know what I proposed instead.  I said he might try bearing witness.

I’m afraid he found me disappointing.  He seemed to think that I sympathized with the other side.

 

 

Father Frog

Monday, 05-14-2018

 

Curiously, many people today think that God pays attention only to big things that affect everyone at once.

I guess this means He keeps the galaxies in their orbits, but doesn’t listen to the prayers of Aunt Lucy.

If we claim God as Father, shall we not at least be consistent?

For to say that God exercises only general care for the universe, not particular care for individuals, is to say that His attitude toward His children is more like a father frog than like that of a human father.  Humans care for their young.  Once the frog spawns, his job is done.

If I were still an atheist, I would be tempted to use this point against Christians.

Are we better fathers than the One from whom all fathers take their names?  I have had too much experience of mercy to think Him no better than that.

 

Must All Men Fight in War?

Monday, 05-07-2018

 

Query:

I have a question about the role of men in society, particularly in the case of a hypothetical war. While I believe that we, as men, do have a role to play in society (protectors of our family would probably be just one easy guess), my understanding of our role in society is still a little limited and ambiguous.  As a male, is it my duty to fight in a war for a just cause?  Particularly, is it my God-given duty to say, go overseas and put my life, body, and mind on the line in an event that will, no doubt, be horrific?  And if not, does that make us cowards?  Would it make us non-virtuous and sinful in the eyes of the Lord?

 

Reply:

As you say, men do have a natural role as protectors of the family.  Persons who protest that this is “gender stereotyping” are not thinking clearly; men don’t bear children, and it is irresponsible to overlook such a profound difference.  I would also say that if there were no other way to protect your family but to fight against someone, then you would be obligated to fight.  If someone pulled a knife on your wife and children and the only way to stop him was to fight, you would do so.

The question of just war, though, is a little different.  Obviously, one difference is that in war you are protecting not just your family, but the society which includes your family.  Granted, some wars need more fighters than others.  But for the protection of society against enemy soldiers, it is not necessary for everyone to be a soldier – just as for the protection of society against criminals, it is not necessary for everyone to be a police officer.  In fact, it would be detrimental to society if everyone were a soldier, because while the soldiers were off protecting society, there would be very little society left for the soldiers to protect.  Not to mention the fact that the soldiers would need someone else to send them food, weapons, and medicines.

I think some people are especially suited by talent and inclination to be soldiers (just as some people are suited by talent and inclination to be military wives).  But others are especially suited to be such things as schoolteachers, engineers, carpenters, farmers, and ministers of religion.  Suppose you ought to be a soldier and would make a bad farmer, but decided to be a farmer anyway.  You would be making a poor decision.  But suppose you were someone who ought to be a farmer and would make a poor soldier, but decided to be a soldier anyway.  This decision would be just as bad.

By the way, when I speak of being “suited by talent and inclination,” to be a soldier, I don’t mean only being aggressive and being able to shoot straight.  Just as there is a certain moral discipline in teaching, so there is a certain moral discipline in soldiering.  For example, just as a teacher must teach only what is true, a soldier must target only enemy combatants, not innocents or prisoners.

One more thing.  You said you were asking only about war “for a just cause.”  A just cause is the first condition for a just war, but it is not its only condition.  For example, the war must be waged with a right intention, at the direction of competent public authority, and with reasonable grounds to believe that it will help more than hurt.  Even when it is right to go to war, justice also requires waging it in the right ways.  That’s why I mentioned the moral discipline of not targeting noncombatants, and there are other conditions concerning how to fight too.

Listen to my Ratio Christi podcast from Texas A&M University

 

 

It’s All About Me

Monday, 04-30-2018

 

I think an honest relationship is a better one.  Even a high-spirited argument between two people can be friendly and courteous.  By bringing their errors to light, the frank exchange of differences helps both parties advance toward the truth.  It also helps each fellow avoid mistaken assumptions and gross misunderstandings of what the other fellow actually believes, because neither of them has to guess.

But some people don't think see it this way.  Quite a few dislike discussing important questions, such as how to live, whether war can ever be justified, or whether there is a God -- the very ones which are most in need of discussion.

Why?  For lots of reasons.  Some claim to find these topics boring.  Some are afraid of seeming unintelligent or uninformed.  Some have no patience with persons who disagree with them -- or they fear that the other persons will have no patience with them.  Some are terrified of stepping outside of mainstream opinion.  Some are afraid that frank discussion may call to their attention things they would rather not think about.

Again, some like to keep what they think secret; for instance they may be afraid of getting in trouble or being thought odd if people find out.  And of course a great many people simply can’t stand the possibility of conflict.  To them, even a polite disagreement is like the screech of nails across a blackboard.  All they can think is “make it stop.”

With courtesy, such obstacles can often be hurdled.  In our day, though, the main reason for reluctance to discuss the important things in life seems to be different, and is much more difficult to overcome.  For many people today hold the view that there are no rational grounds whatsoever for opinions about the important things in life.  This might be viewed as a kind of pop culture solipcism.

It isn’t that such folk have no opinions.  It’s that their opinions aren’t precisely opinions.  For if there are no rational grounds for deciding what is the case, then what a person calls his opinion of the world is not, precisely, about the world; it’s merely a personal characteristic.  His watchword could be “It’s all about me.”  Since he thinks your opinion is about you, and his is about him, disagreeing with his opinion seems to him like criticizing the size of his nose.  He sees it not as disagreement but as disapproval, not as a challenge but as a discourtesy, as if the one who disagreed with him had said “I’m better than you.” 

By taking this attitude, he also shields his opinions from all possible refutation.  "I think these devilled eggs are safe," he says.  "I wouldn’t be so sure,” you say; “the last three diners who ate them got sick."  "Well,” he replies, “I just think they're safe."  “I just think” is his conversation-stopper, for the test of an opinion is its correspondence with reality, but the possibility of such a test is just what he denies.

Or thinks he denies.  For it is easy to be a solipcist, but impossible to be a consistent solipcist.  The way things really are keeps crashing in on us.  And that is why -- if you wait long enough -- it is sometimes possible to speak with these people too.

 

A View of Marriage

Monday, 04-23-2018

 

This is the text of a brief talk I gave recently at the fiftieth anniversary symposium on the document Humanae Vitae, where I had been asked to present a Thomistic view.  I hope to post the video within a few weeks.  When I say the talk is ”brief,” I mean it; the paper on which these few words are based is almost six times longer, and will be posted at this website after it is edited for publication in the conference volume.

 

Thomas Aquinas on Marriage, Fruitfulness, and Faithful Love

This is what we face.  According to the prevailing view, the love of a man and a woman is not an enduring commitment of the will to the true good of another person, but a feeling or an emotion.  Essentially, then, what the culture calls matrimony is cohabitation with formalities.  Like cohabiting couples -- or cohabiting threesomes or what have you -- a married couple may speak of having a committed relationship, but commitment in the traditional sense is just what they do not have.  Sexual intercourse is not viewed as suggestive of the possibility of new life; neither is having children viewed as requiring intercourse, because these days there are labs for that.  Though even in this day of plummeting birth rates, children may still be desired, adults tend to view them as a lifestyle enhancement, something like a home entertainment center, but more expensive.  Though having a few children may still be regarded favorably, having more than a few is frowned upon, because children consume resources, use up disposable income, and require a great deal of care.  A puzzled writer who is not quite so extreme as to condemn all childbearing says nevertheless, “I don’t have the answer to the origin of the longing for children that many experience.  It’s almost certainly due to a complex mixture of biological and social factors.  It might even be an evolutionary trick.”

Against this, we want to argue that the love between the husband and wife is an act of free will by which the spouses give themselves to each other mutually, totally, indissolubly, and exclusively, for the sake of God.  Opening themselves to the possibility of bearing fruit is the most beautiful way that they do give themselves to each other, and the very basis of their love.  By acknowledging that the sexual powers have a procreative purpose, we are not denying that we are ends in ourselves.  Rather we are acknowledging what kinds of ends in ourselves we are.  We are beings whose biological functions are not shackles, but constitutive properties of our embodied personhood.  We do not diminish ourselves by honoring them.  We would alienate ourselves by not honoring them.

All of this has roots in the doctrine of Thomas Aquinas.  Now in one sense, matrimony is complicated, because it has a number of origins.  He argues that natural law itself originates matrimony in matters concerned with having and raising children.  Natural law after the Fall further shapes matrimony so that its natural purposes are not unraveled by the wound of sin, which tempts us to employ our sexual powers in ways that forestall the formation of families or undermine their good order.  The civil law shapes matrimony with respect to such things as spousal support.  The Gospel shapes matrimony by directing it to an additional purpose, for the union of husband and wife represents and makes present the mystery of Christ’s union with the Church.

We can say, then, that natural law institutes marriage in one way, the law of the Gospel institutes it in another, and civil law institutes it in still another.  St. Thomas says that these various “institutions” or origins “are not of the same thing in the same respect.”   However, they are all linked.  Thus, for the civil law to treat marriage as something contrary to what it is by nature would be profoundly wrong; any such so-called civil marriage would not be marriage at all.

As I said, that is rather complicated.  But in another sense, the basics of matrimony are simple, because as St. Thomas says, all of this involves only three matrimonial goods.  The first good of matrimony, he says, is “the birth of children and the educating of them to the worship of God.”   If I ask my students to identify the purpose of the sexual powers, they usually reply “pleasure.”  If, on the other hand, I focus their attention on our natural teleology by asking them to identify the purpose of the eye, the purpose of the ear, the purpose of the capacity for anger, and so on, and then ask them to identify the purpose of the sexual powers, they say instead “reproduction,” which is not bad.  However, procreation means much more.  Reproduction merely means turning out new humans by one means or another.  If this were the only purpose of the sexual powers, it wouldn’t matter whether the partners were united.  In fact, it wouldn’t matter if there were any partners.  We could dispense with parents altogether, gestating children in flasks and raising them in state-run institutions, as they do in Huxley’s Brave New World.  Procreation, by contrast, is the loving act by which posterity is generated.  It means conceiving children in the embrace of their father and mother; it means not only having them together, but nurturing them together, so that they can become virtuous adults; and it means forming families, thereby forging new links between dimmest antiquity and remotest futurity.  Any guppy can reproduce.  We have the privilege of procreating.

The second good of matrimony is the mutual faithfulness of the husband and wife.  Here St. Thomas is using the figure of speech called metonymy, in which a part represents a whole, as when I say “the crown” to represent everything about the institution of monarchy.  St. Thomas does not express his thought by saying that the second matrimonial good is the spouses’ union; rather he uses the most important aspect of their union to represent everything about their union.  “After an injury inflicted upon a man in his own person,” St. Thomas says, “none is so grave as that which is inflicted upon a person with whom one is joined.”  This, he says, is why the Decalogue prohibits adultery immediately after it prohibits murder.

If we view procreation and unity as entirely distinct goods of matrimony, we are making a profound mistake.  Today one hears often hears couples say, “we are putting off children so that we can enjoy each other first.”  But according to the inherited wisdom of the human race, if we seek to enhance matrimonial unity by refusing the gift of children, we are merely turning a pair of selfish MEs into a single selfish US.

The third good of matrimony is sacramental.  As the man and woman are espoused, so Christ and the Church are espoused.  Just because of the indivisible union of the husband and wife, it can represent and make present the indivisible union of Christ and His Church.  And just as the union of their bodies makes the spouses biologically fruitful, so the sacrament makes their union spiritually fruitful, as they pass on their faith to their children and display it to the world.

We mentioned just now that matrimony is indissoluble, but why is it indissoluble?  According to St. Thomas, there are two reasons.  To understand the first one, consider our difference from the other animals.  Among some of the beasts, the female is capable not only of giving birth to the offspring, but also of training them without help from the male.  In such species, intercourse is “random and indiscriminate.”  Among other beasts, the female needs assistance, so the male cooperates with the female in caring for them.  This requires that he recognize the offspring, that he possess a natural inclination to care for them, and that a definite male be joined to a definite female.  In such species, the male and female cooperate until the children are grown.   Now since we are rational beings, not just beasts, this applies even more to us, because our children need nourishment not just for their bodies, but even more for their souls, and their attainment of maturity and virtue takes a long time.

The second reason is stronger.  Even after the children have reached maturity and virtue, they still need the help of their parents to establish their own new families.  “Hence it is of natural law,” says St. Thomas, “that parents should lay up for their children, and that children should be their parents’ heirs.  Therefore, since the offspring is the common good of husband and wife, the dictate of the natural law requires the latter to live together for ever inseparably.”

According to a certain caricature, St. Thomas is quite interested in the procreative good but hardly interested at all in the unitive good.  This is utterly false.  True, the matrimonial friendship differs from other friendships because of its procreative purpose.  On the other hand, everything that applies to loving union in general applies to the loving matrimonial union too.  Taking this into account, St. Thomas actually says more about union than about procreation.  For example, he says, the lovers experience confidence that what has begun well will get better; they experience glory because each one glories in the good of the other; they are consoled because through delight in the good they share, each one possesses a remedy against sadness, and they experience exuberant joy because not only is sadness absorbed, but their exuberance “overcomes every tribulation.”

It is quite amazing how far St. Thomas is willing to go in describing the quality of loving union.  He says, for example, that the lover and the beloved mutually indwell each other.  “The beloved is contained in the lover, by being impressed on his heart” and becoming the object of his affections; the lover, in turn, “is contained in the beloved, inasmuch as the lover penetrates, so to speak, into the beloved.”  Or take the idea that the lover “loves to love.”  In our day we associate such language with soupy sentimentalism and the lavish use of emojis, but St. Thomas gives diamond-hard meaning to it.  The power of will, he explains, is directed to the good.  Love is a spontaneous act of the will, directed to the good of the beloved.  But since to will is itself a good, man can will himself to will.  For this reason, love, by its own nature, “is capable of reflecting on itself.”  “Wherefore,” says the Angelic Doctor, “from the moment a man loves, he loves himself to love.”   This does not mean that he is infatuated with his feelings.  It means that with all his heart, he concurs with the direction of his will.  His attitude toward the beloved might be expressed, “I exult that you exist in this world, I seek all good for you, and I know it is good that I do.”

Another caricature is that St. Thomas frowns on sexual pleasure.  On the contrary, he argues that had it not been for the Fall, the pleasure of sexual intercourse would have been even greater than it is now.  What happened when we fell is not that our pleasure became stronger, but that our reason became weaker.  If we had not fallen, then, our pleasures would have been even stronger, but they would not have disordered our thinking, as they do now.  Our minds would obey God, and our passions and desires would obey our minds.

Still another caricature is that St. Thomas thinks the spouses should have intercourse only because they are trying to have children.  Wrong again.  He does say that sexual intercourse must always be rightly related to its procreative purpose, which means that the spouses must never do anything to make intercourse incapable of bringing about new life.  However, they may also have intercourse simply to celebrate their procreative union.

To see this more clearly, we might think of eating.  We eat because food is necessary, but as St. Thomas points out, necessity has several different meanings.  In one sense we must eat because otherwise we cannot live.  But in another sense we must eat because otherwise we cannot live becomingly.  This is why we eat and drink more on festive occasions:  Not to keep from starving, but to celebrate.  Obviously God endorses this motive; after all, at the wedding feast in Cana, Jesus turned water into wine.  Now even at feasts, eating and drinking must still be rightly ordered to life and health.  It would be prejudicial to life and health if we ate as much as we could and then purged so that we could eat still more.  But right order does not require that we eat and drink only for life and health.  It is not prejudicial to life and health to toast the married couple with wine.

Now apply these distinctions to the enjoyment of sexual intercourse.  In the first sense of necessity, sexual intercourse is necessary simply to be fruitful.  But in the second sense, it is necessary so that the husband and wife may enjoy their partnership in the possibility of fruitfulness becomingly – so that they may celebrate it.  Even celebratory intercourse must still be rightly ordered to procreation, but right order does not require that the spouses enjoy intercourse just for making babies.  Rather it allows them to enjoy intercourse so long as they do nothing to thwart the procreative possibility of their action.

Here is another way to think of the matter.  The husband and wife should cherish their procreative union as good in itself, not just as a tool for pleasure.  But because their union is good in itself, it is also pleasurable, for pleasure, says St. Thomas, is the repose of the soul in what is good.  And so desiring the pleasure of their union is exactly right.  Notice here that pleasure is not the main thing; it is the enjoyment of the main thing.  Pleasure it is not the good itself; it is the delight of experiencing the good. 

Hedonists get this backward.  Rather than viewing pleasure as repose in whatever is good, they view pleasure itself as the good – in fact, as the only good.  From this point of view, one does not really cherish one’s wife for her own sake; he cherishes only the resulting pleasure.  It follows from this theory that if there were a way to have the pleasure of one’s wife without one’s wife, then that would be just as good, or even better.  Never mind marriage – let us just arrange to have electrodes implanted to stimulate the pleasure centers of our brains.  Why experience pleasure indirectly, when we can experience it directly?

St. Thomas is pointing out that I should not treat my wife as that electrode.  She herself is what I should cherish, experiencing the pleasure of that cherishing.  What she and I enjoy, in both the procreative and unitive aspects of our marital friendship, is delightful.  It is delightful to rest in the hope of new life; it is also delightful to rest in our mutual love, as partners in this hope.  But if I say “never mind our hope of children, never mind our mutual love, I just want pleasure,” then I am missing the point.  I understand neither children, nor love, nor delight.

Book:  On the Meaning of Sex

 

Cohabitation Is Not Marriage Prep

Monday, 04-16-2018

 

The idea that cohabitation is good preparation for marriage is amazingly persistent, considering that it isn’t even close to being true.

Research consistently shows that couples who do cohabit have poorer relationships before marriage, poorer marriages if they do marry, and much higher rates of divorce.

When the findings are presented to them, people respond in various ways.  Some cohabiting couples I have known make the decision to stop cohabiting, just because they do care about the relationship.  This seems to me the most sensible response.

Other cohabiting couples tell me that correlation doesn’t prove causation.  No, but it is very unwise to ignore it.

Still others say the statistics are phony.  Nice try.

Perhaps the most common response is to think “We’re the exceptions.”  If there were as many exceptions as people who think they are exceptions, the statistics would be vastly different.

The evidence is so strong that among family sociologists, the debate is not about whether couples who cohabit before marrying have weaker marriages, but why.

The explanation I have always found most intuitive is that in every way, the two relationships are fundamentally different.  The whole point of being married is having a commitment, but the whole point of not being married is not having one.  How can not having one be practice for having one?  It would make better sense to call cohabitation practice for divorce.

Besides, marriage comes with institutionalized norms.  Cohabitation doesn’t; you make it up as you go along.

Just because the future is more uncertain in cohabitation, couples have less incentive to invest in the relationship.  This makes the future more uncertain still.

And because of the uncertainty, persons who are cohabiting tend to keep score.  Keeping score is something you do with your shopkeeper – did I get enough value for what I gave?  Did he come out ahead?  It shouldn’t be necessary with your beloved.  But once the habit is formed, it persists right into marriage.

Friends of mine who study these matters have suggested several additional explanations for both the instability of cohabitation itself and of marriages preceded by cohabitation.

One explanation is that couples who don’t cohabit must make a clear and sharp decision to enter into the commitment of marriage, but cohabiting couples slide from one stage to another with very little conscious decision.  First they sleep together.  Then they do so more frequently.  After a while he spends the night so often that he starts keeping a toothbrush and change of clothes at her house.  Then he moves more of his things over there.  Eventually he might as well move in, and he does.  Marriage is just one more thing the couples slide into.

Here is another explanation.  But you won’t like it.

Across human cultures, men tend to prefer the best-looking women.  Women, by contrast, care less about men’s looks, but prefer men with higher status and greater financial security.

Now as men grow older, their status and financial security improve.  But as women grow older, their looks decline.  Do you see where this is going?  For each year that a cohabiting relationship continues, the woman becomes less attractive to the man, but the man becomes more attractive to other women.

The facts are especially cruel to the woman, who is probably hoping that if only she lives with the man long enough, he will marry her.  Actually, the longer the two of them cohabit, the more she is placed at disadvantage -- and the more he is likely to want out.

“But don’t older married men sometimes dump their wives too?”  Sure, but marriage is much more stable than cohabitation.  Why?  Because it really is a commitment.  Even today our mores reflect this.  Men who walk out on cohabitation are rarely looked down upon.  Cads who ditch their wives for younger ones may sometimes be envied, but they are never admired.

Besides, marriage civilizes men.  The longer they are married, the more they grow to understand Browning’s line, “Grow old along with me!  The best is yet to be, the last of life, for which the first was made.”

Now tell me:  How is a relationship which is based on having no commitment, contains multiple incentives for failure, and contains a built-in disadvantage for women good preparation for marriage?

Book:  On the Meaning of Sex

 

Optimism, Pessimism, Neither of the Above?

Monday, 04-09-2018

 

During a beautiful conference last week about marriage, sexuality, love, faithfulness, and fruitfulness, there was a great deal of discussion, both between and during sessions, about whether we should be optimistic, pessimistic, or hopeful about the state of things today.  An optimist, I suppose, thinks the culture can be redeemed in 60 years, but a pessimist thinks it will take 600. 

All of us think about such things, and I confess that I too alternate between pessimism and optimism.  In my view, though, we should ignore and disregard both of these moods.  We don’t know what will happen.  God knows.  All that matters is hope.  Nothing can separate us from the love of God in Christ Jesus, neither powers, nor principalities, nor technological paradigms, nor renegade theologians, nor disorders in the Church.

We are not generals, but soldiers.  God is the general.  We think we have to see the battlefield as He sees it.  We don’t.  Nor do we need to devise Benedict options.  In that difficult age in which the Rule for monastic life was developed, Benedict himself didn’t think he was devising a Benedict option.  God did, and that was enough.

Nor do we need to be afraid.  How did the Christian knight react when he came upon the dragon?  Did he estimate whether the dragon could be overcome in his lifetime?  No.  He lifted his sword and fought the dragon, and he sang with the joy of the battle.

Some day, when Christians look back on our age, they will look back on it not as a golden age -- certainly not that -- but as a heroic age.  Under our circumstances, even the exercise of the ordinary, everyday elements of moral character, such as temperance and chastity, is coming to resemble heroic virtue.  And think how much more deeply those future Christians will understand sexuality than we do, having read the histories of our battles, our defeats, and our triumphs.

The Christian knight was neither a pessimist or an optimist, and he was right to despise his moods.  Let us try, by God’s grace, to be knights.