“He Must Be Crazy!”

Monday, 09-15-2025

 

Query:

Some people blur the distinction between mental illness and moral wrong by ascribing certain behaviors to mental illness when they are in fact simply evil acts.  Have you ever addressed this interesting topic?

 

Reply:

I haven’t written much about your question, but let me make amends.  It’s a good one for sure.  I was brought up to believe that all criminality and wrongdoing reflect a kind of mental disease, and we do say things like “The man who stabbed that woman on the subway must have been crazy!” and “What a nutcase, to shoot someone just because he disagrees!”

If a stabber or the gunman were really nuts, we think, then he wouldn’t be to blame.  Or would he?  It’s true that all justifications for doing wrong reflect some sort of disordered thinking.   But are they disordered in that sense?

The traditional insanity defense tried to pin down the kind of disorder which absolves a person of blame, declaring that he would have to be incapable of telling the difference between right and wrong.  Unfortunately, this standard doesn’t pin down what it is supposed to pin down, because the idea of not being able to tell the difference between right and wrong is deeply ambiguous.

Let’s see whether we can untangle the matter by making some distinctions.  What does it mean to say that someone can’t tell the difference between right and wrong?

Suppose we take it to mean that a person understands all the words in a sentence like “It is wrong to deliberately take innocent human life” but just doesn’t know that the sentence is true.  I don’t think this is possible:  There are no such people.  If this were what the insanity defense meant, it would be nonsensical.

But there are other cases.  First, here are two cases in which a person is clearly not culpable for wrong acts.

  • Perhaps he is so profoundly impaired that he doesn’t know the meaning of the words in the sentence.  It is unlikely that such a person would have enough mentality to act at all, but if he did, and committed wrong, then he should certainly not be held responsible for it.  On the other hand, he should be institutionalized.
  • Or perhaps he suffers such grave delusions that he cannot recognize what is actually the case.  For instance, he may understand perfectly well that it is wrong to deliberately take innocent human life, but he mistakes the man whom he kills for an escaped lion, which must be slain to protect others.  Such a person is not culpable, but again, he should be institutionalized, both for his own protection and for that of others. This, I think, is the sort of case to which the so-called insanity defense was meant to be applied, but it is very narrow.

Now here are four cases in which a person should be viewed as culpable for wrong acts, even though some might deny it.

  • Perhaps the person understands the basic moral rules, but does not grasp some of their obvious their corollaries.  For example, he might know it is wrong to kill, but be confused about whether it is wrong to allow an injured person to die and do nothing to help.  Even though there is such a thing as innocent error in hard cases, we rightly demand better moral understanding than that.  Thus in most cases, such persons are culpable.
  • Or perhaps he would grasp the wrong of his deed if only he thought about it, but alas, he doesn’t think about it -- either because the deed is habitual, or because he has fallen into passion.  An example of habitual inattention is that he has done so much petty pilfering that he no longer gives it a thought.  This is a vice, and it is culpable.  An example of distraction due to passion is that when he finds a man in bed with his wife, he falls into a rage and kills him.  This too is culpable, although it not so bad as killing in cold blood, because the provocation is so extreme.
  • Or perhaps he knows at some level that he is doing wrong, but tries to persuade himself that he doesn’t.  We should all be familiar with this sort of self-deception.  Who among us has never made an excuse for something he knew, deep down, to be wrong?  Unfortunately, depraved ideologies teach denial and make it more extreme.  For example, nothing is more common than for a person in the grip of a corrupt worldview than to think “I may do evil for the sake of good.”  Wrong for which we make excuses is still entirely culpable.
  • Or perhaps he is a sociopath – he knows full well that he is doing wrong, but lacks normal inhibitions against it and normal feelings of sorriness about it.  Contrary to common opinion, a sociopath does have a conscience, because conscience is knowledge, and he has that.  What he lacks is remorse, a feeling which accompanies guilty knowledge in normal persons, but not in him.   In fact, just because sociopaths do have an idea of right and wrong, they sometimes work pretty hard to represent their actions to themselves and others as just:  “Of course I took his car.  How else was I supposed to get home, man?”  Interestingly, some sociopaths are aware that there is something wrong with them, or missing in them.  They realize that they ought to feel inhibitions and remorse, and even work at controlling themselves, whether just to fit in, or even to be more nearly normal.  At any rate, wrong done through lack of normal inhibitions and feelings is still culpable. 

Finally, here are two cases in which a person may or may not be culpable, or may be culpable to a greater or lesser degree.

  • Perhaps the person knows that he is doing wrong, but is incapable of controlling his compulsions.  As though by itself, his hand grasps a knife and plunges it into another, even though he is trying to keep the act from happening.  Such a person may have varying degrees of culpability, because to have literally no control over one’s impulses is very rare.  Another issue in determining his culpability is how he got this way.  For example, if he fell into his condition because of habitual abuse of drugs, then he is indirectly responsible, because he shouldn’t have abused them in the first place.  In any case, he needs to be locked up.
  • Or perhaps he doesn’t know he is doing wrong because he isn’t aware of his actions at all.  As in the last case, if this condition results from his own prior actions -- for instance, if he is too drunk to know he is drunk – then he is culpable, because he should not have become drunk.  But if his ignorance of his actions results from, say, a brain injury, then he is not culpable, but should be institutionalized.  Then again, suppose he has medicine for a mental disorder, but refuses to take it.  Even if he is not responsible for the disorder, to some degree he may be responsible for failure to take his medicine.

So most criminals are to blame.  Only a few rare ones are not, but even they should be restrained, whether in a prison or a mental institution.

People of a certain widespread persuasion think that because of the unequal distribution of wealth, no criminals are to blame.  They suppose that crime isn’t due to sin, but to capitalism.  For example, they make excuses for burglars because houses are so expensive these days.  You can work out for yourself into which of the cases I’ve discussed these ideologues fall.

 

 

 

Is Taxation Theft? When It Is and When It Isn’t

Monday, 09-08-2025

 

One of the great moral errors of our day might be called expropriationism.  If you prefer catchier labels, call it the Robin Hood Fallacy.  According to this notion, government is entitled to confiscate wealth for no other reason than “doing good.”  This leads to a style of politics in which the groups in power decide for us which of their own causes our wealth is to support, taking it by force.  Sometimes they even offer the pretense that they are helping the needy, but usually they confuse the needy with some subset of the merely wanty – or with their partisan clients, which is even worse.

Many Christians seem to miss the point, thinking that expropriation is wrong just because the wrong groups are in power, choosing the wrong causes for subsidy.  This is where the horror stories are offered, and horrible they are:  Of subsidies to promote abortion, subsidies to produce obscene and blasphemous “art,” subsidies for all sorts of wickedness and blasphemy.  But expropriation would be wrong even if each of its causes were good.  Consider the following progression.

1.  On a dark street, a man draws a knife and demands my money for drugs.

2.  Instead of demanding my money for drugs, he demands it for the Church.

3.  Instead of being alone, he is with a bishop of the Church who acts as bagman.

4.  Instead of drawing a knife, he produces a policeman who says I must do as he says.

5.  Instead of meeting me on the street, he mails me his demand as an official agent of the government.

If the first is theft, it is difficult to see why the other four are not also theft.  Expropriation is wrong not because its causes are wrong, but because it is a violation of the Commandment, Thou shalt not steal -- even if you think you can use the money better than your victim can.

But how, one may ask, can government steal?  We live in a republic; aren't we therefore just taking from ourselves?  No, not even in a republic are the rulers identical with the ruled, nor for that matter are the ruled identical with each other; if we were just taking from ourselves, there would be no need for the taking to be enforced.

Then is all taxation theft?  A lot of people on both left and right think so -- anarcho-capitalists, anarcho-communists, libertarians, voluntarists, and others -- but no.  Government may certainly collect taxes for the support of its proper work.  The key is to identify its proper work.  That work is not the support of all good causes or the doing of all good deeds, because each of the other forms of association in society has its own proper work, which ought not be taken away.  Families have work that no one else can do.  So do churches and synagogues.  So do neighborhoods.  So do protective associations for working people, farmers, and businessmen.  I don’t say that such associations can never desecrate their own work, as when teachers enforce ideological purity instead of teaching, or lobby legislators to increase public education budgets which are already filled with lard.  I only say that they have their own work.

This establishes a strong presumption against most of the things into which government likes to stick its fingers.  Let the other associations confine themselves to doing what only they can do.  Let government confine itself to what only it can do, chiefly by upholding public justice.

But if government were to end its subsidy of good causes, wouldn't these good causes suffer?  Not necessarily; they might even thrive.  As Marvin Olasky has shown in one of my favorite books, The Tragedy of American Compassion, government subsidy itself can make good causes suffer.  One reason is that in taking money by force, one weakens both the means and the motive for people to give freely.  Not only that, but government usually distorts good causes in the act of absorbing them.

But what if the causes did depend on the proceeds of theft?  Should we do evil, that good may come?  There is no such thing as a tame injustice which will do only what we want it to, going quietly back into its bottle when we have finished with it.  Sin is no more like that than holiness is.  In politics, no less than in private life, it ramifies.

 

Laws of Thought

Monday, 09-01-2025

 

Today’s post concerns the nature of logic.  It will bore some readers, interest others, and fascinate a few.  Read on to find out which kind you are.

Aristotle famously distinguished between theoretical syllogisms (which describe how we consider what is the case) and practical syllogisms (which describe how we decide what to do).

Here is an example of a theoretical syllogism.  The crucial thing is that the premises and the conclusion are all propositions:

SYLLOGISM #1:

All men are mortal.

I am a man.

Therefore, I am mortal.

Here is an example of a practical syllogism.  This time the crucial thing is that although the premises are propositions, the conclusion is not a proposition.  It is an act, a decision:

SYLLOGISM #2:

Theft is wrong.

Taking Steve’s wallet is theft.

So I don’t take it.

The reason the first syllogism ends in a proposition, but the second one ends in a decision, is that Aristotle viewed logic as the laws of rightly ordered thought.  For much of its history, logic was always presented that way!  Today, however, the topic is usually presented differently.  Students today are taught to view it, not as the theory of rightly ordered thought, but as the theory of the consequence relation – something purely formal.  Another way to put this is that Aristotle viewed logic almost as a branch of ethics, but today’s logicians view it almost as a branch of metaphysics.  (The two, of course, are connected – at least from the classical point of view.)

Reading Aristotle’s logic with contemporary assumptions easily leads to misunderstanding, because when today’s students are taught about Aristotle’s practical syllogisms, they usually think that their conclusions must be propositions – like this:

SYLLOGISM #3:

Theft is wrong.

Taking Steve’s wallet is theft.

Therefore, taking Steve’s wallet is wrong.

Now “Taking Steve’s wallet is wrong” isn’t a decision that I make, but a conclusion about what is the case.  I might ignore it – that is, I might acknowledge that taking his wallet is wrong, but take it anyway.  Just for this reason, Aristotle himself would regard Syllogism #3 not as a practical syllogism, but as a theoretical syllogism.

Well, that’s fine.  But even so, Syllogism #3 has something to do with practice, doesn’t it?  For a rightly ordered mind reasons, “If taking Steve’s wallet is wrong, I won’t take it.”  Calling Syllogism #3 a theoretical syllogism and letting it go at that misses that important point.  For this reason, I think modern Aristotelians need a name for mental processes like Syllogism #3.  We might call them not just theoretical, but practitheoretical syllogisms -- theoretical syllogisms, but with a twist.

But just as there are syllogisms which Aristotle would call theoretical yet have something to do with practice, aren’t there also syllogisms which Aristotle would call practical yet have something to do with what is the case?  Like this one:

SYLLOGISM #4

All men are mortal.

I am a man.

So I concede my mortality.

The reason Aristotle would call this a practical syllogism is that “I concede the fact of my mortality” isn’t a conclusion about what is the case (what is the case is up there in the premises), but a decision that I make.  I might have refused assent to the fact of my mortality, but, having a rightly ordered mind, I assent to it.

And again, that’s fine.  But just as Syllogism #3, even though it is a theoretical syllogism, has something to do with practice, so Syllogism #4, even though it is a practical syllogism, has something to do with what is the case.  It is all about whether I give in to what is the case.

So, just as I think modern Aristotelians need a name for mental processes like Syllogism #3, so  think that they need a name for mental processes like Syllogism #4.  We might call them not just practical, but theoripractical syllogisms – practical syllogisms, but with a twist.

Now if you take the contemporary view, thinking of logic as merely the theory of the consequence relation, then none of this will make a bit of difference to you.  To you, Aristotle’s practical syllogisms aren’t syllogisms at all.  Theoretical syllogisms are the only kind there are.

But if you take the classical view, thinking of logic as the laws of rightly ordered thought, then these distinctions are important.  They reflect four different ways in which a rightly ordered mind may approach matters, whether theoretical or practical.

School over.

 

Misgendering and Other Misses

Monday, 08-25-2025

 

In some states and countries, legislators have moved to criminalize misgendering – that is, calling people by their biological sexes instead of the sexes they say they are.

What a blow for equality!  But why stop there?  Why do we stigmatize misgendering, and yet turn a blind eye to misspeciesing?

After all, some folks claim to be cats, foxes, raccoons, and other animals.  It insults them to be called human.  I say, all of the bigots who call them people should be put in jail.

Besides being right and just, calling folks by their true species would also save on the costs of raising kids.  If little Jeffy identifies as a dog, he can be kept in a doghouse and fed kibble, and there is no need to send him to school.  I can see this becoming very popular, especially among people who don’t like their children.

And what about all the people who claim to be different people?  If they say they are, then they are.  That’s just science!  From now on, anyone who says he is Donald Trump must be addressed as “Mr. President,” and anyone who says he is Jesus Christ must receive the prayers of the faithful.

The pioneer of this movement for justice was Grace Slick, former singer with Jefferson Airplane, once called the Queen of Acid Rock.  After Slick delivered a daughter -- excuse me, an offspring assigned the female sex at birth -- a Catholic nurse came around with a form, asking what name she had chosen for her.  Slick replied, “god. We spell it with a small g because we want her to be humble.”

Unfortunately, Slick didn’t have the courage of her convictions.  Claiming she had been joking, she later said that her daughter should be called “China.”

Poor little girl, to be relegated to such a wretched fate!  For all her days to be called a mere country, when really she was the lord of the universe!

These cruelties have got to be stopped.  Everyone has a right to be affirmed in, well, whatever.  No more putting it off.  Do it now.

 

 

Mixed Feelings

Monday, 08-18-2025

 

I confess to having mixed feelings about the recent case in which the Court ruled that Oklahoma cannot deny charter status to a school just because it is Catholic.

On the one hand, the decision is clearly correct.  Certainly this sort of discrimination by the state on the basis of faith should not be allowed, provided that the faith accords with natural law.  (I would certainly discriminate against a religion of assassination.)

However, whether the Church is well-advised to take advantage of benefits such as those which charter schools receive is another question.  Since money always has strings attached -- and the strings get shorter and stronger over time -- other ways must be found to make Catholic education available to those who desire it.

Making it available is especially necessary in view of the degeneration of the public schools.  Please let’s not blather about religious “neutrality.”  So called secular education is not neutral, but reflects a bias against faith in favor of irreligion.

In fact, even that way of putting it is not precisely accurate.  It isn’t that public schools have no god; in fact they place many gods before God.  Superficial thinkers suppose that unconditional loyalties – whether of the “woke” or another variety -- don’t count as religion just because they don’t use the word “god” for their gods.  But the crux of the matter does not lie in the words they use.

 

Read the Fine Print

Monday, 08-11-2025

 

Most people know the importance of carefully reading contracts before signing them and labels before using the product.  All sorts of poisons can be hidden in the fine print.  What most people don’t know is that fine print is also a means of advancing the international culture war.  (And yes, it is international.  Did you think globalization was only about markets?)

If you read the UNESCO documents on childhood sexuality education, for example, you will find pages and pages about protecting children from sexual abuse.  Sprinkled through them are much briefer passages which let the cat out of the bag -- but you have to look for them.  It’s true that the activists who run these agencies don’t want children to be raped.  But they do want to sexualize them, and they want it very much.

They explain that “comprehensive sexuality education” “equips” young people including children to develop sexual relationships.  Among its many goals are that five-to-eight year olds are to be taught that they can masturbate and it will give them pleasure; nine-to-twelve year olds, that abortion is safe; and twelve-to-fifteen year olds, that there are various and sundry “gender identities” which deserve equal respect.

Speaking of so called gender identities:  The UNESCO documents don’t list them, but did you know that activists now claim that some people are “xenogender”?  That’s a gender “that cannot be contained by human understandings of gender.”

I wonder:  If it can’t be contained by human understandings of gender, then how do the activists know that it is one?

 

 

Against “Natural Ingredients”

Monday, 08-04-2025

 

By “natural ingredients,” people mean ingredients derived from nature.  But every ingredient is derived from nature.  Snake venom is derived from nature.  Arsenic is derived from nature.

It would be an exaggeration to say that you can derive anything from anything, but if you apply enough processing to ordinary proteins and carbohydrates, you can derive all sorts of noxious substances.  To get poisons, you don’t have to start with poisons.

The term “natural ingredients” would be meaningful and helpful only if it were used to mean ingredients which beings of our nature can consume safely.  If we don’t use it that way (and we don’t), then we might as well get rid of it.

So in case the title of this post confused you, I’m completely on board with natural ingredients.  I oppose only “natural ingredients.”