
The Underground Thomist
Blog
None Rejoice Who Have Not GrievedSunday, 04-20-2025
None rejoice in Easter-tide less than those who have not grieved in Lent. This is what is seen in the world at large. To them, one season is the same as another, and they take no account of any. Feast-day and fast-day, holy tide and other tide, are one and the same to them. Hence they do not realize the next world at all. To them the Gospels are but like another history; a course of events which took place eighteen hundred years since. They do not make our Savior's life and death present to them: they do not transport themselves back to the time of His sojourn on earth. They do not act over again, and celebrate His history, in their own observance; and the consequence is, that they feel no interest in it. They have neither faith nor love towards it; it has no hold on them. They do not form their estimate of things upon it; they do not hold it as a sort of practical principle in their heart. This is the case not only with the world at large, but too often with men who have the Name of Christ in their mouths. They think they believe in Him, yet when trial comes, or in the daily conduct of life, they are unable to act upon the principles which they profess: and why? because they have thought to dispense with the religious Ordinances, the course of Service, and the round of Sacred Seasons of the Church, and have considered it a simpler and more spiritual religion, not to act religiously except when called to it by extraordinary trial or temptation; because they have thought that, since it is the Christian's duty to rejoice evermore, they would rejoice better if they never sorrowed and never travailed with righteousness. On the contrary, let us be sure that, as previous humiliation sobers our joy, it alone secures it to us. Our Saviour says, "Blessed are they that mourn, for they shall he comforted;" and what is true hereafter, is true here. Unless we have mourned, in the weeks that are gone, we shall not rejoice in the season now commencing. It is often said, and truly, that providential affliction brings a man nearer to God. What is the observance of Holy Seasons but such a means of grace? -- St. John Henry Newman
|
Rock, Paper, Scissors: What Will He Do Next?Monday, 04-14-2025
I am not going to take a position here on whether Mr. Trump is a genius, a madman, or something in between. I do want to criticize the notion that he “acts on whims” and is “volatile.” How he gives such an impression is easy to see: In negotiating with both friends and enemies, he blows both hot and cold, depending on time of day. What those who think he is acting on whims overlook is that he believes in blowing both hot and cold. Consider the game “Rock, Paper, Scissors.” If the other player knows you will always play Rock, then he will always play Paper, and he will always win. But if you play Rock one-third of the time, Paper one-third of the time, and Scissors one-third of the time, so that he can't predict what you will do, then he won’t be able to gain an advantage. In the mathematical theory of games, playing Rock all the time is called a “pure” strategy, and playing each of the three moves one-third of the time is called a “mixed” strategy. It can be shown that in the sort of winner-take-all game in which there is no advantage to cooperation, there is always some best strategy, though it may not be one which will always win. Often the best strategy is a mixed strategy. This is intuitive. Keep ‘em guessing. In fact, keep ‘em guessing not only about what you are going to do, but even about some aspects of what you know and believe, and who you listen to, and what it would take for you to change course. Needless to say, not all purely competitive games are like Rock, Paper, Scissors. In that game, the best strategy is to play each move with equal probability, but in another kind, the best strategy may be different – say, to play Move A one-quarter of the time, Move B one-quarter of the time, and Move C one-half of the time. It depends on how the game is set up -- and also on the situation on the board. On most issues, Mr. Trump’s long-term preferences are known. For example, he has been talking about tariffs for decades. When he blows hot and cold, I think he is playing a mixed strategy. Mixed strategies are hard to play in a political system which requires consensus. The reason is that in order to keep the other side guessing, one has to play one’s cards close to one’s chest. Since one’s allies might leak, one may have to keep them just as much in the dark as one’s adversaries are. Being in the dark, they might panic. They might withdraw their support. Markets may roil. For all these reasons, the game one is really playing (whether he knows it or not) may be much more complicated than the game one may seem to be playing, and it may even change as it’s going along. You might argue that Mr. Trump is playing the right game or the wrong one, or with the right mixed strategy or the wrong one, or that he is playing it well or playing it badly. But I don’t think it persuasive to suggest that he is volatile or acting on whims.
|
A Vatican DOGE?Monday, 04-07-2025
Whatever you may think of the DOGE up in Washington, we need something like a DOGE purge at the Vatican. This will require a strong pope who is utterly committed to the defense of the faith. He will have to overhaul Vatican finances, but that’s only the beginning. He will have to cut waste in the Vatican bureaucracy, encourage the bishops to do the same in their dioceses, and back them up in doing so. He will have to eliminate offices and dismiss people not in accord with Catholic teaching. He will have to deny the name "Catholic" to schools and organizations which violate Catholic doctrine, and press the bishops on this point too. Finally, he will have to forbid organizations of the Church from accepting direct government money, such as subsidies to administer programs the state approves. Such funds are inherently corrupting. Not only are they addictive, but they always come with strings attached, both visible and invisible.
|
Theophilus Speaks to the Pontius Pilate SocietyMonday, 03-31-2025
Gentle readers: Years ago, I used to write a monthly column called “Office Hours” for an online magazine for Christian college students published by an Evangelical Protestant organization. From time to time, I still receive letters from people who tell me how much the column helped them get through their college years and young adulthood. Some of you may know that this website provides links to a number of the dialogues, but many are missing, and all need a bit of revision. Lately I’ve been fixing them all up, with plans to upload all of them at once. That will take quite a chunk of time, in between other work, but every now and then I will post one of the revised ones here in the blog. Typically, the column was a dialogue between an imaginary professor, M.E. Theophilus, and his students. Theophilus is an anomalous member of the PMS Department (for Post-Modern Studies) at Post-Everything State University. If you like riddles, it may amuse you to figure out what “M.E.” stands for, but no, the answer is not “me.” The column below, one of those I happened to revise just this week, is a little different than most, because Theophilus isn’t having a conversation, but giving an invited speech to a student organization. There is a little back-and-forth chat at the end. Sometimes he’s a bit of a smartass, but I hope you find him an interesting smartass. +++ + +++ Madame Procurator, members of the Pontius Pilate Society of Post-Everything State University: I’m honored to have been invited to speak to such a distinguished student organization. Looking up, I see that you’ve placed my podium beneath a banner bearing your motto, the Roman procurator Pilate’s famous query, “What is truth?” It was a great question. I hope you will not be angry with me if I say that he did himself no credit by asking it. Not everyone who asks “What is truth?” wants to know the answer. Governor Pilate asked the question not to begin a conversation, but to end one. Perhaps he thought that it had no answer. It was the last sentence he addressed to his prisoner, Jesus of Nazareth, before turning on his heel and walking out of the room. I propose not to end a conversation, but to begin one. That requires several things. One is that we desire the truth; the other is that we honor the truth we have. If we desire the truth, then we must reject the obstacles to its attainment. If we honor the truth we have, then we must be honest with each other about the obstacles that arise. That is why I plan to speak tonight about three false beliefs which hinder the search for truth. I call them myths. These myths, along with many others, are so entrenched in Post-Everything University that they could almost be considered part of the curriculum. Although they hinder the search for every kind of truth, I will be giving special attention to how they hinder the search for truth about God. I do not imagine that in a single brief talk I can persuade you to accept everything I say. My hope is more modest: perhaps I can “connect the dots” between my claims and some other things that you probably believe already. I also hope to provide points on which I might be challenged. Myth No. 1 is the idea that thinking you know the truth is arrogant and intolerant. Is it really so arrogant and intolerant to think you know the truth? Let’s start with simple cases. I happen to know that the potato salad is spoiled, and the last three diners got sick just from eating it. Would it be arrogant for me to warn the others? You happen to know that the public library is this way, but the motorist who asked me for directions is headed that way. Would it be intolerant for you to suggest that he turn around, and tell him why? Of course no one takes this line about potato salads or highways. On the other hand, people do take this line about who God is and how to live. “God and how to live are matters of opinion,” they say. “Where things are and what you can safely eat — those are matters of fact.” Yes, of course concern facts, but they are opinions about the facts. After all, people may have different views about just what the facts are. The other diners might be of the opinion that the potato salad is wholesome. The lost motorist might be of the opinion that his general direction is correct. Surely that wouldn’t make me arrogant to contradict them. Differences of opinion arise even in the sciences. Paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould is of the opinion that Darwinian evolution is a fact; biochemist Michael J. Behe is of the opinion that it’s not. Each scientist says that he’s right; each scientist says that the other is wrong. Does that make him arrogant or intolerant? Not necessarily — although, of course, he might be. The rule is that each one should offer evidence for what he thinks, listen to the evidence offered by his opponent, and not try to shut him up. That’s how science is supposed to work. Arrogance doesn’t come from having convictions; it comes from having the wrong convictions about how to treat people who don’t share them with you. Humility doesn’t come from not having convictions; it comes from having the right convictions about the importance of gentleness and respect. What gives the myth of the intolerance of knowing truth its strength? Its power comes from a picture — not a photograph or a painting, but an image many people carry in their minds. In the picture, a man is being burned at the stake. He’s there because other people, who say they have the truth, are angry with him for saying that they don’t. I agree that such a thing should never happen. But in my mind is a different picture. In mine a man is also being burned at the stake — I almost said, being hung on a cross. He’s there because other people, who say there isn’t any truth, are angry with him for saying that there is. Myth No. 2 is the idea that the important thing in life isn’t having truth, but searching for it. You’re more likely to hear this particular myth from burned-out teachers than from other students. One form it takes is that the good life is a life spent seeking the good life. But do you notice something fishy about the statement? The speaker is talking in circles. On one hand, he says he already knows what the good life is — it’s the life spent seeking the good life. But if he already knows what it is, then he doesn’t have to seek it. In fact he can’t seek it, because he has it already. But if he can’t seek it, then he doesn’t have it, because seeking is what it is. So he has to seek it. Do you want to know what I think? He needs to seek somewhere else. Would you listen for even a moment if someone tried to tell you it was better to itch than to scratch, to be hungry than to eat, or to seek friends than to have any? No? Then why would anyone believe that it’s better to seek truth than to find it? Why should this desire and search be different than any other? The purpose of any search is to find what you are looking for. We search for truth not for the sake of searching, but for the sake of truth. May I tell you what I think is at the bottom of the second myth? I think God has given us two different kinds of desire for truth — one for truth with a little “t,” and another for truth with a capital “T.” Truth with a little “t” is abstract knowledge. The desire for this kind of truth is satisfied by knowing things like what makes a great poem beautiful, what stars really are, how plants and animals are made, and how many gods there are — good knowledge, some of it even crucial knowledge, but the kind you can write on a blackboard. Now Truth with a capital “T” is something else altogether. It’s God Himself in person. The desire for this Truth can be satisfied only by personal knowledge, living knowledge — the greatest knowledge, but the kind you can have only through relationship with Him, and ultimately, with beholding Him face to face. Some teachers and scholars burn out because they confuse the two desires. They try to satisfy their longing for Truth with a capital “T” merely by piling up more and more truth with a little “t.” The problem is that although truth with a little “t” has its own satisfaction, it can’t give you that satisfaction. Confusing the two desires is like trying to relieve an itch by eating a hamburger! If you keep on asking from truth what only Truth can give, eventually it can’t even give you what it gave before. The only sweetness left to you is the sweetness of the memory of the longing itself. So you tell yourself, “Now I understand. The important thing in life isn’t having truth, but searching and longing for it. We long for the sake of longing; we search for the sake of the search.” And then you tell your students. And then you tell your friends. And then you write it in your books. But it’s wrong. Myth No. 3 is the idea that faith hinders the search for truth because it gets in the way of reasoning. This idea itself hinders the search for truth. It stands facts on their head, for reasoning itself depends on faith. Most of you here in the Pontius Pilate Society describe yourselves as skeptics. You pride yourself that you take nothing on faith, and depend only on reasoning. A proper skepticism is good, and I myself try to be a skeptic in the proper sense. For example, I am skeptical about the idea that it is possible to reason without taking anything on faith. Suppose someone were to say to you, “All reasoning is baloney.” He would be wrong, of course, but could you prove it? Guess what? You couldn’t do anything of the kind. The only way to prove your point would be to present an argument, but arguments themselves depend on reasoning. So your argument would beg the question — it would assume what it was supposed to prove, that reasoning isn’t baloney. Where does this leave us? We reason not because the validity of reasoning can be proven, but because we take its validity on trust. We trust that the consequence relation — “if this, then that” — corresponds to something in reality. And trust is another word for faith. Reasoning depends on trust, on faith, in other ways too. How do you know the moon is made of rock instead of cheese? You say people have been there and found out. But did you go along to make sure it really happened? Of course not; you just trust that they were telling the truth. If you’re scientifically inclined, maybe you’ll add that the moon doesn’t reflect light in the same way as cheese. But have you compared the reflections from rock and cheese yourself? Of course not; you just trust that someone has. What if I speculated that on the moon, cheese reflects light like rock does on earth and rock reflects light like cheese does on earth? Maybe you’ll answer that the laws of physics don’t change from place to place. But have you personally checked all the places in the universe to be sure? Of course not; you just trust that nature doesn’t play tricks. I’m not saying that all kinds of faith are reasonable; I’m saying only that they can’t all be unreasonable. The plain fact is that unless you have some faith, you can’t even reason at all; unless you have some faith, you can’t even decide what to doubt. In order to know anything, you have to believe something. So whether to have faith isn’t an issue. You will have faith in something. I don’t know what it will be: if not God, then something else. The only real question is which kind of faith to have. The wrong kind will hinder the search for truth — the right kind will help. MODERATOR: Thank you, Professor Theophilus, for presenting your -- unusual point of view. I think all of us here can say that we have never heard anything like it. Interrogators, have you any questions? THEOPHILUS: Interrogators? MODERATOR: In honor of the Procurator, Pontius Pilate, that is what we call ourselves. INTERROGATOR #1: Professor, you’ve presented some interesting arguments, but it seems to me that they all rest on a fallacy. THEOPHILUS: If they do, then I will have to correct my thinking. What is the fallacy, please? INTERROGATOR #1: All of your arguments about the search for truth take for granted that there is a truth to be found. I maintain that there is no truth. THEOPHILUS: My goodness. Could that possibly be true? INTERROGATOR #1: I think so. THEOPHILUS: Then you concede that there is truth. But in that case your statement, “There is no truth,” must be false. INTERROGATOR #1: Let me rephrase. I don’t claim to have a truth. It is only my belief that there is no truth. THEOPHILUS: Forgive me, but that doesn’t let you off the hook. A belief is about a state of affairs. To say that you believe that there is no truth is to say you believe that it is true that there is no truth. You are still in same pickle as before. INTERROGATOR #1: But a belief isn’t about anything. It’s just a feeling. THEOPHILUS: If your statement was not about anything, then it could not have been about my arguments, so you have said precisely nothing. MODERATOR: Next question. INTERROGATOR #2: Professor Theophilus, I deeply respect your beliefs, but I think truth is whatever a person sincerely believes. THEOPHILUS: I’m impressed. You must be a powerful magician. INTERROGATOR #2: Excuse me? THEOPHILUS: If you sincerely believe you’re a large diet coke, will you be one? If you sincerely believe the onion rings are fries, will they be fries? INTERROGATOR #2: I wasn’t talking about those kinds of things. THEOPHILUS: Of course not. Nobody falls for the “truth is whatever you sincerely believe” gimmick when the subject is fries and diet coke. But if your magic doesn’t work even on little things like fries and diet coke, then I should think it very unlikely that it would work on big ones like right and wrong and God. MODERATOR: Next question. INTERROGATOR #3: Truth is just whatever works. If your beliefs work for you, great. I’m not interested unless they work for me. THEOPHILUS: You’ll have to help me out, because I don’t know what it means for a belief to “work” for you. Do you mean it comforts you, that it motivates you, that it makes you a better person? INTERROGATOR #3: Any of those things. I’m not going to dictate my own definition of what it means for a belief to work. What works for me may not work for you. THEOPHILUS: Well, I don’t see what any of those things has to do with truth. If I have a tumor, I may be comforted by the belief that I’m in perfect health, but the tumor is still there. If I’m driving in the wrong direction, I may be motivated by the belief that I’m driving in the right one, but Chicago is still the other way. If there aren’t any fairies, I may become a better person because I believe that they’re watching me, but they really aren’t. Working doesn’t make a statement true. INTERROGATOR #3: Then what does? THEOPHILUS: To ask whether a statement is true isn’t to ask whether it works, but whether it’s accurate, whether it’s factual, whether what it says is so. I don’t think the idea “Truth is whatever works” is a way to get to the truth. More often it’s a way to shut truth out. I may know someone who used to have ideals but now cares for nothing but money. Is that really all that matters? “Hey, it works for me.” You may know someone who gets fried every weekend and has started to use drugs on the weekdays too. Does it really make sense to destroy himself? “Lay off, it works for me.” MODERATOR: Next question. INTERROGATOR #4: If you don’t mind, I’d like to follow up on what you said to the first two interrogators. THEOPHILUS: Please do. INTERROGATOR #4: You said we can find out some truth. I agree. And you implied that there is a difference between little things and big things. I agree about that too. THEOPHILUS: Thank you. What is the problem? INTERROGATOR #4: There’s no doubt that we can find out some truth. I just don’t think we can find out any truths about the biggest and most important things, like God. THEOPHILUS: Except one. INTERROGATOR #4: Pardon me? THEOPHILUS: I said, “Except one.” You do believe you know one truth about God. INTERROGATOR #4: I’m not aware that I believe that. THEOPHILUS: Nevertheless, you do believe it. The one thing you think you know about God is that you can’t know anything else about God. INTERROGATOR #4: I see what you mean. Yes, of course I believe that one thing. But I don’t see how it makes a difference. THEOPHILUS: My question for you is this: Why should that one thing be an exception? INTERROGATOR #4: An exception? THEOPHILUS: Yes. If you can’t know anything else about God, then on what grounds can you know this one thing about God? INTERROGATOR #4: You make it sound as though I have to know a lot of things about God in order to say that I can’t know any other things about God. THEOPHILUS: That’s exactly what I do think. I mentioned a little while ago that in a certain sense I am a skeptic. One of the things I am skeptical about is complete ignorance. Don’t you in fact have a rather elaborate picture of God in your mind, full of all sorts of colorful details? INTERROGATOR #4: How could that be? What details do you mean? THEOPHILUS: One detail, I’d guess, is that you think of God as infinitely distant — because otherwise you wouldn’t be so sure you couldn’t know anything about Him. Another is that you think of Him as unconcerned about you — because otherwise you’d expect Him to have provided the means for you to know Him. Third, you must picture Him as completely unlike the Biblical portrayal — because in that account He does care about you and has provided the means for you to know Him already. Should I go on? INTERROGATOR #4: No, I see the point. I concede that I believe quite a few things about God. THEOPHILUS: The only problem, you know, is that you have no good reason for believing the particular things about Him that you do. INTERROGATOR #4: How could you possibly know that? THEOPHILUS: Because until a moment ago, you didn’t even know that you did believe them. This would be a good time to begin an inquiry. INTERROGATOR #4: How can I — MODERATOR: Thank you, Professor Theophilus. Our time is up. Interrogators, don’t forget: Next week we discuss Matter: Why It’s All There Is. Good night.
Copyright 1999 J. Budziszewski. All rights reserved.
|
The Two SwordsMonday, 03-24-2025
Query:I have a short question for you. What should the commitments of the faithful be towards papal temporal authority? In particular, may I disagree with what Pope Boniface’s bull Unam Sanctum said way back in 1302 about the superiority of the spiritual to the temporal authority? Keen to hear your thoughts.
Reply:Unam sanctam scandalizes a lot of people. I do understand it to be binding on the faithful when understood correctly. This is difficult, and I am way over my head here. However, it seems to me that most of the difficulties people have with Unam sanctam come from failing to distinguish those things it holds to be true in principle, which are always and everywhere the same, from the juridical arrangements these true principles require, which may vary. People read its remarks about the superiority of the spiritual to the temporal power as though it were about the latter. I think it’s mostly about the former. Concerning what is true about government in principle, I reconstruct the teaching of the bull as follows: 1. There are two different “swords” or powers, temporal and spiritual, which are, and should be, wielded by two different sets of officials, civil and ecclesiastical. 2. However, it is logically absurd to maintain that neither power has greater authority than the other in any sense, because then we wouldn’t know what to do when their orders come into conflict, as they inevitably will. 3. Which power then is superior? Here’s the scandalous part: Spiritual authority is superior to temporal authority – I think for two reasons. One reason is that our spiritual good is incomparably greater than our temporal good. The other is that the spiritual power is more incomparably more reliable within its own domain, because of its charism. 4. But the term “superior” gives rise to endless difficulties, and theologians are not usually very good at the kinds of distinctions which political philosophers demand. What does the bull actually mean by the superiority of the spiritual to the temporal authority? One part of the meaning is that civil officials have the spiritual obligation to exercise their authority on behalf of the Church and for its protection. The other is that ecclesiastical officials have the spiritual right to stand in judgment on civil authorities and declare when they have erred. Now concerning the juridical arrangements these principles require, matters are more obscure. A careless reading of Unam sanctam may give impression that the spiritual obligation and right to which I have just referred are always to be given civil or constitutional effect, so that, for example, the Church may put an erring magistrate in prison. “Do this, do that! Jump!” But I don’t think that reading is even close to correct, and here’s why. In the first place, I take the point about the authority of the Church to declare when civil officials have erred to include only moral and doctrinal errors, not poor prudential judgments. So, for example, the Church may condemn the WW2 German government for carrying out the Holocaust and for persecuting the Church herself, and she may even absolve her members of obedience to tyrants. But she has no business telling the government how best to reduce air pollution. She may demand that illegal immigrants be treated with fairness and compassion, but she may not demand, in the name of fairness and compassion, that states neglect to enforce their borders, or that they are not to deport any violators. In the second place, we must distinguish between two states of affairs: Do the citizens and temporal authorities acknowledge the truth of the faith, or deny it? As a matter of principle, it is far better for them to acknowledge it -- as was the case during the era during which Unam sanctam was promulgated. But it is also a matter of principle that if the state and citizens are recalcitrant, they must not be compelled to acknowledge its truth. As St. Hilary of Poitiers said, “God does not want an unwilling obedience.” The proper way to bring about the agreement of citizens and state to the faith is evangelism, moral persuasion, and witness, even at great sacrifice and risk. And in the third place, the circumstances in which the faith finds itself make a difference. Suppose the citizens and temporal authorities of a certain land do acknowledge the truth of the faith. It still doesn’t follow that the Church should have civil power in that land. In many cases, perhaps almost always, the spiritual authority of the Church will have greater effect when it is backed up only by spiritual sanctions. I don’t say that this is so in every case whatsoever: For example, I am sure Gideon acted rightly in pulling down the Asherah poles and destroying the altars of Ba’al. But most of the time, giving temporal enforcement powers to the spiritual authority would harm the Kingdom of God rather than advancing it. So is the spiritual power superior in principle? Yes. But does that mean it ought to have an actual political check? Not necessarily. I may be way off, and I say all this subject to correction.
|
Love and EvidenceMonday, 03-17-2025
Query:I have been arguing with my friends about the existence of God. How can we weigh the evidence for and against a position? How do we know how much evidence is needed to prove a position? It’s impossible to prove all of the arguments for a position.
Reply:A complete answer to your questions today would require a library, not a blog post! But let me see whether I can say anything helpful, and yet brief. I know how you have wrestled with your own doubts too. In one sense, your question cannot be answered. There isn’t any rule, any procedure, or any algorithm which can weigh evidence and say “Okay, you have enough now.” The only instrument we have is our own minds. So there is a subjective element even in assenting to what is true independently of our minds. In another sense, though, your question can be answered. Ultimately, the decision to assent to a truth comes down not to whether there is “enough,” but whether the grounds for assent are more compelling than the grounds for refusing assent. Sometimes this can even mean whether our minds are better able to endure not having answers to one set of questions than not having answers to another set of questions. The reality of God provokes questions like “Why is there evil?”, some of which we can answer and some of which we cannot. But His nonexistence would provoke questions like “Why is there good? Why is there anything at all?” The grounds for assent can themselves be weighed, and the mind has a number of resources for doing so. One, of course, is reasoning, but reasoning by itself is not enough, because except for the first principles of all reasoning, the faculty of reason cannot supply its own premises. These come from other sources, such as conscience, experience, and authority. Conscience, for example, gives me grounds to believe in God, because a law requires a lawmaker. The experience of grace gives me grounds to believe, especially in the sacraments, for in Christ things become possible which I cannot do by my own power, such as breaking free of habitual sin. Authority is reviled these days, but sound authority actually extends my reason, conscience, and experience, because minds like yours and mine don’t operate in a vacuum – we are not solitary but social beings. I would be a fool to disbelieve in the existence of China because the reports of people who have been there as “a mere argument from authority,” and in the same way, I would be a fool to carelessly disregard the treasure of wisdom in the Scripture and Tradition of the Church. Practical certainty -- what used to be called moral certainty -- does not mean that I have come to a point at which no further counterargument can be found or imagined, but that I have come to a point at which it is reasonable to assent. Assent is more than just intellectual, because it involves an act of the will. I must not only believe, but trust. I must allow myself not only to hold a belief, but to say “Yes!” to it. As the apostle James says, the devils believe – and tremble. Assent means that we believe, we accept – and, in the case of assent to God, that we rejoice. You speak of believing in a “position,” but there is a great difference between believing in an abstract proposition and believing in a person. Granted, I must believe in certain propositions in order to believe in a person; for example I must believe that the person is real and not a figment of my imagination. Even so, personal knowledge exceeds abstract knowledge. Believing and assenting to God is more like falling in love with someone and marrying her than like believing in Newton’s Three Laws of Motion. Even in the experience of love, over time I learn more and more about the beloved. As I do so, I come to trust what I know about her more and more – I trust her more and more – and I come to trust my trust, so that I no longer doubt her. Finally, in marrying, I trust myself to her, because marriage is a mutual gift of self. It isn’t for nothing that Scripture describes our relationship to God Himself as a marriage, and promises a wedding feast. But He is not the bride but the bridegroom. Rather than putting an end to new knowledge, trusting myself and opening my soul to the beloved opens up the possibility of even greater knowledge. The knowledge available from outside of the relationship of trust is very limited, but the knowledge available from inside of it the relationship is deeper and more intimate. Every husband and wife know this. So it is, I think, with us and God. Of course God knows us through and through already. He doesn’t have to learn about us, but we have to learn about Him. In this life that knowledge is by faith, which is a kind of knowledge because it carries with it its own experience and authority; it is not just abstractly thinking something about Him but having a foretaste of Him, for as the letter to the Hebrews declares, “Now faith is the substance of things hoped for, the evidence of things not seen” (a passage the meaning of which is blurred in some translations). Yet even so, this “kind of knowledge” is not the same as seeing Him. It is more like seeing an image in a mirror. In the next life, faith will no longer be needed, because we will behold Him face to face. We will know as we are known. In that hope we live, groaning with anticipation, because it is not yet fulfilled. It staggers me that our Lord was not content to be an Unknown God, as in the inscription on the famous Athenian altar. It stuns me that He was not content merely to send messages, but came among us. It leaves me in awe that the Creator of the Universe did not abhor the Virgin’s womb.
|
Beauty, Sublimity, and NeedinessMonday, 03-10-2025
Query:I was part of the virtual meeting you had with my high school’s Philosophy Club, and I was very taken with your remarks about the difference between beauty and sublimity. Could you say a little more about that?
Reply:Well, I’m not an expert on aesthetics, but sure, I’ll do the best I can! I think it was in the 1700s that people who thought about art and literature became fascinated by the fact that beauty doesn’t exhaust the range of aesthetic values. The kind of thing which is properly called beautiful, or lovely, or pretty, stirs a certain kind of pleased admiration, as a rose does. It gives rise to this delight because of its grace of form and color. But the kind of thing which is properly called sublime stirs awe, as the North Face of Mt. Everest does. We tremble, because of its vastness or mystery. It’s possible for the same thing to be both beautiful and sublime, just as the same thing can be both big and green. But beauty and sublimity are different qualities, as bigness and greenness are different qualities. So an object can be beautiful without being sublime, and it can be sublime without being beautiful. The writer Coleridge relates an anecdote about two tourists whom he overheard viewing a great waterfall. One tourist called it “sublime,” but the other called it “pretty.” Coleridge inwardly agreed with former tourist, but he was revolted by the judgment of the latter tourist. In fact, these two qualities are so different that an object which is sublime may sometimes include elements of the jarring or grotesque, even though, in themselves, these are opposed to beauty. A painting of the crucifixion in which Jesus doesn’t seem to suffer might please us in the way beautiful things do, but would probably not be viewed as sublime. A painting in which stuns us by the vividness with which it conveys His pain and suffering might excite awe and be viewed as sublime, but would probably not be viewed as beautiful. Needless to say, in everyday speech people throw these words around in slangy, comical, or figurative ways, and that’s okay. When the hero of the movie finally turns the tables on the bad guy, I might clap and cry out, “beautiful!” When someone serves us an incomparably scrumptious piece of chocolate cake, I might delightedly exclaim, “sublime!” This is like my calling it a “miracle” when I manage to balance my checkbook. Does this help?
Her reply:Thank you! Honestly, I didn’t have clear definitions until now. I still don’t quite understand how something can be both beautiful and sublime, though. Could you elaborate? Also, why do we find different things beautiful? Is there a gift of aesthetic judgment? And does art have to be beautiful?
My further response:As to how something could ever be both beautiful and sublime: Beauty and sublimity are very different, yes, but they don’t absolutely exclude each other. For example, quite a bit of religious art has both qualities. Consider the Madonna and Child painting by Bouguereau called The Virgin and the Lilies. It’s pleasing color and form give it beauty, but the gravity of the faces and the holiness of the Child’s blessing inspire awe, which gives it sublimity. Or consider Michelangelo’s Pieta. Mary, in unfathomable grief, is holding her dead Son. One is struck with awe by the stillness of her face and by the suggestion of a vastly greater secret than mere mortality. Yet the arrangement is perfectly balanced and beautiful. Believers like me consider God Himself both beautiful and sublime. St. Augustine of Hippo wrote in awe, “Question the beautiful earth; question the beautiful sea; question the beautiful air, diffused and spread abroad; question the beautiful heavens; question the arrangement of the constellations; question the sun brightening the day by its effulgence; question the moon, tempering by its splendor the darkness of the ensuing night; question the living creatures that move about in the water, those that remain on land, and those that flit through the air, their souls hidden but their bodies in view, visible things which are to be ruled and invisible spirits doing the ruling; question all these things and all will answer: 'Behold and see! We are beautiful.' Their beauty is their confession. Who made these beautiful transitory things unless it be the unchanging Beauty?” Now all those transitory things are beautiful – but the unchanging Beauty who made them is also sublime. As to why we don’t all find the same things beautiful: I think there are at least three reasons (maybe lots more). One is that we have unequal ability to recognize beauty when we see it, and someone whose appreciation of beauty is blunt, inexperienced, or still developing, may be able to recognize some kinds of beauty more easily than others. A child will be drawn to bright colors: “How pretty!” But a grownup, while appreciating what the child appreciates, may be more attracted to a subtle interplay of hue and shadow. A second reason is that even among people who are equally sensitive to beauty, one person’s “antennae” may be tuned more closely to one kind of beauty, and another’s to another kind. Amazingly, this difference adds to the delight, because each person can help the other person to see what he sees! A third reason is that some people are attracted to things that aren’t beautiful, but call them beautiful, just because they are attracted to them. More about that below. As to whether we have a gift of aesthetic judgment: Yes, I would call it a gift. Aesthetic perception enables us to see in things qualities that no animal can see. It elevates us to the consideration of things beyond food and drink. We didn’t give it to ourselves; it is a gratuitous gift to the human race from our Creator. As to whether art has to be beautiful: Here let me borrow from something I posted to my blog in 2019. If by art we mean any object that we value for reasons other than its usefulness, then there is no telling what people may call “art.” Even beauty and sublimity are far from the only qualities that people look for. I am not here thinking of attractions which can be separated from the work, such as how much its great expense will delight my friends, or how well its color scheme blends in with the rest of my decor. Rather I am thinking of attractions which are intrinsic to the work, which it would possess even if it I had picked it up cheap at a garage sale and it looked out of place in my house. For example, a work of art might be neither beautiful nor sublime, but intriguing. It might be none of these things, but a faithful representation of its object. It might call my attention to something I had not thought of before. It might add variety and interest to a structural feature of a building. It might catch the eye, or even fool the eye as in the form of illusion called trompe-l'œi, like this painting by del Caso. It might suggest an episode in a story, or convey a lesson. It might symbolize a concept. It might excite admiration because of the labor which went into its composition. It might evoke a mood, such as boredom, a philosophy, such as nihilism, or a psychological state, such as obsession. It might call up a whisper of memory or longing. It might calm or excite the beholder. It might challenge, comfort, or irritate. It might build up, or it might inflict damage and harm. It might signal that the maker holds one of the currently fashionable views (or, more rarely, that he doesn’t). It might do nothing more than express his attitude toward himself, other people, God, or the viewer -- in the manner of a joke, a prayer, a sob, a sin, or a curse. Such qualities have always been present in art. The difference is that in our day they have migrated to the center of the enterprise. Mind you, though I could do without some of them, I am not at the moment passing judgment on all of them, only pointing them out. I am not one of those who hate all modernist art, though much of it leaves me cold. It is often interesting -- even though it is not often what I would call beautiful. Or, for that matter, sublime.
Her reply:Last question for now! In our Philosophy Club meeting, a lot of questions about God came up too, just like in your comments just now. You mentioned that God is utterly complete, with no unfulfilled potentiality. Since God is already fulfilled, why does He desire to have a relationship with us? Aren’t desires born out of need or lack?
My further response:Have you noticed how strongly people want to think that God is needy? Quite a few people think He must have created us out of loneliness. A widely quoted poem begins, “And God stepped out on space, and he looked around and said: I’m lonely -- I’ll make me a world.” But God doesn’t need us. We Human beings are lonely because of deficiency, especially in relation to God, from whom we are alienated by sin. But God is deficient in nothing. He did not create us because He needed us; He created us from sheer love. Perhaps our problem is that we think of love itself as the result of deficiency: I love, because I need someone. If Divine love were like that, then Divinity would incapable of love. This is why Aristotle considers it ridiculous to think that God could have friendship with man. He thinks of God as “thought thinking itself,” revolving around itself in utter indifference to humans and their affairs. Then again, perhaps the reluctance to believe that God doesn’t need anything arises from a desire to put God in our debt. The asymmetry of our relation to Him perturbs us; we want Him to depend on us, as we depend on Him. Irrationally, we are more confident if we think He needs something from us – if we think we can make Him unhappy by withholding it -- than if it is His very nature to love. This delusion makes us think that we can bargain with Him. In Christian tradition, which is my own tradition, Divine love isn’t like that, because it proceeds not from deficiency but from utter fullness. St. John doesn’t just write that God loves, but that God is love. He is One God, yes, but this One is a burning unity of three Divine Persons united in love. Thus it pertains to His very being to love, and it pertains to Him not because of need or compulsion, but freely, as gift. Charity is the stupendous, supernaturally infused virtue by which a human being becomes capable of loving like that, by sharing in the Divine life. Yet according to the same faith, the most stupendous act of Divine love is that the Second Person of the Trinity, by His nature lacking nothing and incapable of pain, joined Himself to the weakness of our own human nature. He took the burden of our suffering upon Himself, even the suffering of our alienation from Him. Identifying completely with us, He deliberately exposed Himself to death by torture, so that if we are in turn identified with Him, then everything in us that needs to die can also die, and we can be resurrected with Him. A God who lacks something is not much of a God. But a God who freely joins Himself to our suffering, just because of the fullness of His love for us, is worthy of the highest worship.
|