Authority and the Common Good

Monday, 04-18-2022

 

Query:

Thomas Aquinas connects the authority to make laws with responsibility for the common good.  Surprisingly, some of my colleagues find this connection perplexing.  How would you explain it?

 

Reply:

I find that surprising too.  Considering our constitutional traditions, one would have thought that only denying the connection would puzzle them.  But these days we don’t understand our constitutional traditions very well either.

Think of it like this.  What is the first and principal concern of law?  Directing things toward their purpose, the common good.  Who is responsible for directing things toward a purpose?  The one to whom the purpose belongs.  To whom does the purpose of the common good belong?  To the whole people.  What follows?  That the people themselves, or someone acting in their place and on their behalf, are responsible for directing things toward the common good.  But to lay down directions for the common good is precisely to make laws; so the people themselves, or someone acting in its place and on its behalf, is responsible for making law.

Maybe that will be enough, but let’s dig in a little.

According to Thomas Aquinas, God made us free.  He is fond of quoting a line from one of the Old Testament wisdom books, Sirach 15:14, "God made man from the beginning, and left him in the hand of his own counsel."  This doesn’t give us permission to do whatever we wish.  What it means is that unlike sub-rational creatures, which act by instinct, we must exercise judgment in order to discern and follow the good.

He also likes to quote Psalm 4:6-7, where the psalmist asks “Who shows us good things?” and answers his own question by exclaiming “The light of Your countenance, O Lord, is signed upon us."  He takes this as meaning that what enables us to distinguish good from evil is the light of natural reason, so that “the natural law is nothing else than the rational creature's participation [in] the eternal law.”  In short, God does not jerk us around.  Rather He makes us participants in His providential care for us.  We are to treat each other this way too, ruling others not as though they were slaves, but as free men.

You see where this is going.  Both the competence to discern what is good, and the responsibility to discern what is good, rests, under God, with human beings.  The competence and the responsibility go together.  In domestic matters, the individual is responsible for directing himself to his own good; in the affairs of the commonwealth, the community as a whole is responsible for directing itself to the common good.

Of course the manner in which the community makes laws depends on the form of government.  It could make laws in a purely democratic manner, in assemblies of the people.  It could instead choose one person, and rest the direction of affairs in his hands.  In between these extremes are a variety of other possible modes of government.  The decision among them has to be made according to prudence, in the light of circumstances.  By the way, saying that the direction of affairs might be put in a single pair of hands doesn’t mean setting up a tyrant.  In fact, Thomas Aquinas makes clear in his Treatise on Kingship that kings who have become tyrannical should be removed, and the removal of a king who has become tyrannical is the prerogative of the people, precisely because the appointment of the rulers in the first place is the prerogative of the people. 

St. Thomas is persuaded that in general, there does need to be a king, because every complex whole requires a directing part, like the cop directing traffic.  Probably this is why St. Thomas assumes delegation of the community’s power in his definition of law, “an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and promulgated.”  Even so, the Latin is compatible with either “him who has” or “they who have.”  And he would probably view our president as a king.

This king should be a constitutional rather than absolute monarch.   In fact, St. Thomas says the best form of government is “partly kingdom, since there is one at the head of all; partly aristocracy, in so far as a number of persons are set in authority; partly democracy, i.e. government by the people, in so far as the rulers can be chosen from the people, and the people have the right to choose their rulers.”  The king doesn’t have to be hereditary or serve for life.  In this sense, St. Thomas would probably consider our own president a king, at least so long as he does not resort to ruling tyrannically (which is always a danger, especially today).

Such, he thinks, is the proper state of affairs.  Indeed, “that power is called politic and royal by which a man rules over free subjects, who, though subject to the government of the ruler, have nevertheless something of their own, by reason of which they can resist the orders of him who commands.”

Is that an absolute?  No.  There are exceptions.  Although it would be tyranny to rule responsible subjects as though they were slaves, it is not tyranny to make decisions for them if they have proven too vicious or irresponsible to take an interest in the common good.  Thus St. Thomas cites St. Augustine of Hippo to the effect that “If the people have a sense of moderation and responsibility, and are most careful guardians of the common weal, it is right to enact a law allowing such a people to choose their own magistrates for the government of the commonwealth.  But if, as time goes on, the same people become so corrupt as to sell their votes, and entrust the government to scoundrels and criminals; then the right of appointing their public officials is rightly forfeit to such a people, and the choice devolves to a few good men."

Maybe some of these thoughts will help you in discussions with your colleagues.

 

Hell Was Bound in Chains

Sunday, 04-17-2022

 

Let no one fear death, for the Savior's death has set us free.  He that was taken by death has annihilated it!  He descended into hades and took hades captive!  He embittered it when it tasted his flesh!  And anticipating this Isaiah exclaimed, "Hades was embittered when it encountered thee in the lower regions."

It was embittered, for it was abolished!

It was embittered, for it was mocked!

It was embittered, for it was purged!

It was embittered, for it was despoiled!  It was embittered, for it was bound in chains!

It took a body and, face to face, met God!

It took earth and encountered heaven!

It took what it saw but crumbled before what it had not seen!

 

-- St. John Chrysostom, Paschal Homily

 

 

Many, Many Steps

Thursday, 04-14-2022

 

The Soviet Union used to put political dissidents into insane asylums.  But there is more than one way to make political use of the issue of mental health.  One path to the total state is the therapeutic state.

The headline in a recent article reads “Children as Young as 8 Should Be Screened for Anxiety, Experts Recommend.”  One of the quoted experts emphasizes that the screening should include everyone, not just those who are exhibiting symptoms.  (Say, why not put everyone straight into therapy, just in case?  It would save time.)

The idea is that since the level of anxiety has increased during the pandemic, we need to do something.  Yes, steps must be taken.  “These guidelines are a preliminary step to many, many steps that we need to take nationally as a community of people who are concerned about our youth,” says another of the experts.  Yes, many, many steps.

Nationally.  Because we are concerned about our youth.  We are anxious.  About their anxiety.

But for now, just a teeny, preliminary step.  Having terrified all the children, we will screen them all for terror.

I have a better idea.  Don’t screen them.  Stop terrifying them.

 

Pints with Aquinas

Monday, 04-11-2022

 

On Thursday, I travelled to Ohio for a three hour conversation with the inimitable Matt Fradd of the Pints with Aquinas podcast.  The first half was about cabbages, kings, and all sorts of things, and the second half was about my new book How and How Not to Be HappyYou can listen to it here or at the Talks Page.  The stream is preceded by two minute wait, which you can use to pour your own pint.

It was a lot of fun.  Matt’s podcast is consistently fantastic, and if you haven’t yet discovered it, you should.  I think he’s going to be breaking the three hours of this particular interview into shorter segments with topical labels which will be posted at his website later.  What you see here is unprocessed, unpasteurized, and entirely natural.

Last week I was also interviewed by Thomas Mirus, of the excellent Catholic Culture website, and I’ll make another announcement when that interview goes live.

 

That's Not What the Common Good Means

Monday, 04-04-2022

 

One of the hardest tasks in political theory is weaning people from a utilitarian view of the common good.  Sometimes people tell me, “I’m not a utilitarian.  I know we shouldn’t commit intrinsically evil acts for the sake of the results.  But for the sake of the common good, don’t we have to make exceptions?  What if we have to target innocent people to save our country?  What if we have to lie to keep other citizens from voting for bad people?”

That is committing an intrinsically evil act for the sake of the results.  People who speak like this are really saying that there are no such things as intrinsically evil acts -- that ultimately, a good enough result can justify anything whatsoever.  If we say we are only willing to commit abominations “as an exception,” we are merely saying that in other cases the resulting good just isn’t quite good enough.

Besides, you can’t save your country by doing evil things.  The country isn’t just a collection of people, but a moral community.  If in order to vanquish our evil enemies we commit evil deeds, we convert ourselves into our enemies.  That isn’t winning, it’s losing.  We destroy the very thing that are fighting for.

This takes us back to the common good, because justice isn’t a personal scruple or an idiosyncrasy that we can dispense with when we wish and yet remain ourselves.  The most important part of the common good is clean hearts.

Even if I were a utilitarian, I wouldn’t be a utilitarian.  What I mean is that the results of acting on the belief that only results matter are also unacceptable.  Each time we do the unthinkable, we make it more thinkable.  Pretty soon it becomes routine.  We lower the bar for justifying shameful deeds until it collides with the floor.  We become like the streetwalker who says “I’m not promiscuous.  I only have sex with men who pay me.”

 

Another One!

Thursday, 03-31-2022

 

Gentle readers,

I don’t want to tire you out with blurbs and publicity – but for those who are interested, a new interview about my new book How and How Not to Be Happy has just gone live.  The interviewer is  Michele McAloon of the Cross Word Podcast, and you can listen right here.  I enjoyed talking with her.

Have I mentioned that you can buy the book?  Well, you can.  (Don’t you want to be happy?)

 

So What Is the Problem with Usury?

Sunday, 03-27-2022

 

Query:

Can you offer some guidance on a very loaded topic:  Usury?  I am a convert who works in the financial services sector, and I am wondering if I’ve been continually participating in, or at least cooperating with, grave sin.  For over a century, the Church has said very little about usury.  But it was regarded as a grave sin for more than a millennium, none of the definitions have changed, and by those definitions it seems to be systematically and hopelessly entrenched in our daily lives.

 

Reply:

This is a complex question.  The Seventh Commandment forbids theft.  Traditionally, this was viewed as the grounds for all prohibitions of financial subterfuge and pilfering, not only, say, the prohibition of fraud, but also the prohibition of usury.  Deuteronomy 23:19 reads, “You shall not lend upon interest to your brother, interest on money, interest on victuals, interest on anything that is lent for interest.”

Over the course of Church history, the rule has often been taken as forbidding all charging of interest whatsoever to fellow members of the community.  However, it is at least possible to argue that this interpretation misses the point.  The question is the sense in which the passage refers to “your brother.”

Let’s distinguish between loaning to someone because he is in want, and loaning to him because he wants to invest the money in an enterprise and make a profit.  If “your brother” means your fellow who is in want, then the passage prohibits exploiting the poor:  After lending them what they desperately need, one may not then demand that they give back even more.  But if “your brother” means all of your fellows, then it prohibits all charging of interest to those who belongs to the nation of Israel.

Scripture often praises lending to the poor, and two other passages of the Law which condemn taking interest do make clear that the context of the prohibition is loans to the poor:

●  “If you lend money to any of my people with you who is poor, you shall not be to him as a creditor, and you shall not exact interest from him.  If ever you take your neighbor's garment in pledge, you shall restore it to him before the sun goes down; for that is his only covering, it is his mantle for his body; in what else shall he sleep?  And if he cries to me, I will hear, for I am compassionate.”  (Exodus 22:25-27, RSVCE.)

●  “And if your brother becomes poor, and cannot maintain himself with you, you shall maintain him; as a stranger and a sojourner he shall live with you.  Take no interest from him or increase, but fear your God; that your brother may live beside you.  You shall not lend him your money at interest, nor give him your food for profit.”  (Leviticus 25:35-37, RSVCE.)

Taken this way, the prohibition of usury forbids taking unfair advantage of those who are vulnerable, and this makes it a natural extension of the Commandment against stealing, because stealing is another kind of injustice with respect to property.  The prohibition of using one standard of measure for buying and another standard of measure for selling, which is a form of fraud, is another such extension:  “You shall not have in your bag two kinds of weights, a large and a small.  You shall not have in your house two kinds of measures, a large and a small.  A full and just weight you shall have, a full and just measure you shall have; that your days may be prolonged in the land which the Lord your God gives you.  For all who do such things, all who act dishonestly, are an abomination to the Lord your God.”    (Deuteronomy 25:13-16, RSVCE.)

The question may arise, “If the idea is to forbid financial subterfuge and plundering, then why not simply declare ‘Commit no financial subterfuge or plundering’?”  Because although that is a good moral principle, it does not have enough precision for the regulation of a community.  The very purpose of the additional precepts is to provide the necessary exactness.

Various nations, philosophers, and religions have prohibited charging interest on loans, considering it the taking of unfair advantage.  From the perspective of the demand theory of value widely held today, this is difficult to understand; it seems absurd to view charging interest as unfair, because a thing (in this case the use of borrowed money) is deemed to be worth whatever price people are willing to pay for it (in this case interest).  However, for people who are borrowing not to expand their business, but to eat, and who might starve if they do not borrow, this way of thinking seems harsh.

Aristotle thinks another reason for holding the charging of interest in suspicion is that unlike someone who invests his money in a productive activity such as a farm, the lender seems to get something for nothing.  He writes, “There are two sorts of wealth-getting, as I have said; one is a part of household management, the other is retail trade: the former necessary and honorable, while that which consists in exchange is justly censured; for it is unnatural, and a mode by which men gain from one another. The most hated sort, and with the greatest reason, is usury, which makes a gain out of money itself, and not from the natural object of it. For money was intended to be used in exchange, but not to increase at interest. And this term interest, which means the birth of money from money, is applied to the breeding of money because the offspring resembles the parent. Wherefore of all modes of getting wealth this is the most unnatural."  (Politics, trans. Jowett, Book 1, Chapter 10.)

On the other hand, if the charging of interest is not allowed, then why would anyone loan money at all?  Certainly not as a shrewd business practice.  He would have to be motivated by love of neighbor.  In this case lending money becomes a form of friendship or aid to the poor.

Some, seeking to harmonize the ancient suspicion of interest with modern banking practice, suggest that although perhaps some charging of interest is getting something for nothing, not all of it is.  After all, the lender is giving up the use of money which he might otherwise have put to productive use, and so, they say, it is not unreasonable to compensate him for his loss.  From this point of view, the crime of usury should be viewed not as charging interest per se, but as charging interest in excess of the lender’s opportunity cost.

That is a plausible objection to Aristotle’s economic argument against charging interest.  However, it is not a sufficient objection to the charitable argument – that one should lend money not to make money, but to help one’s brother, especially if he is in need.  From this point of view, one might say that modern banking practice presupposes that nobody counts as one’s brother.

In response to the hypothetical objection that Torah should have prohibited not just charging interest to strangers, but all charging of interest, St. Thomas replies that the Law did not intend that the Israelites take interest on loans to aliens, but only tolerated the practice.  The people were prone to an excessive desire for wealth (as people are today), and would be more peaceful toward aliens if they were able to earn something through their dealings with them.

Other issues come into the picture too, but this may give you a start.

Related:

Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Treatise on Divine Law

Which is NOT THE SAME as

Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Treatise on Law

(but you can read that too)